The Stacks project

7.47 Topologies

In this section we define what a topology on a category is as defined in [SGA4]. One can develop all of the machinery of sheaves and topoi in this language. A modern exposition of this material can be found in [KS]. However, the case of most interest for algebraic geometry is the topology defined by a site on its underlying category. Thus we strongly suggest the first time reader skip this section and all other sections of this chapter!

Definition 7.47.1. Let $\mathcal{C}$ be a category. Let $U \in \mathop{\mathrm{Ob}}\nolimits (\mathcal{C})$. A sieve $S$ on $U$ is a subpresheaf $S \subset h_ U$.

In other words, a sieve on $U$ picks out for each object $T \in \mathop{\mathrm{Ob}}\nolimits (\mathcal{C})$ a subset $S(T)$ of the set of all morphisms $T \to U$. In fact, the only condition on the collection of subsets $S(T) \subset h_ U(T) = \mathop{\mathrm{Mor}}\nolimits _\mathcal {C}(T, U)$ is the following rule

7.47.1.1
\begin{equation} \label{sites-equation-property-sieve} \left. \begin{matrix} (\alpha : T \to U) \in S(T) \\ g : T' \to T \end{matrix} \right\} \Rightarrow (\alpha \circ g : T' \to U) \in S(T') \end{equation}

A good mental picture to keep in mind is to think of the map $S \to h_ U$ as a “morphism from $S$ to $U$”.

Lemma 7.47.2. Let $\mathcal{C}$ be a category. Let $U \in \mathop{\mathrm{Ob}}\nolimits (\mathcal{C})$.

  1. The collection of sieves on $U$ is a set.

  2. Inclusion defines a partial ordering on this set.

  3. Unions and intersections of sieves are sieves.

  4. Given a family of morphisms $\{ U_ i \to U\} _{i\in I}$ of $\mathcal{C}$ with target $U$ there exists a unique smallest sieve $S$ on $U$ such that each $U_ i \to U$ belongs to $S(U_ i)$.

  5. The sieve $S = h_ U$ is the maximal sieve.

  6. The empty subpresheaf is the minimal sieve.

Proof. By our definition of subpresheaf, the collection of all subpresheaves of a presheaf $\mathcal{F}$ is a subset of $\prod _{U \in \mathop{\mathrm{Ob}}\nolimits (\mathcal{C})} \mathcal{P}(\mathcal{F}(U))$. And this is a set. (Here $\mathcal{P}(A)$ denotes the powerset of $A$.) Hence the collection of sieves on $U$ is a set.

The partial ordering is defined by: $S \leq S'$ if and only if $S(T) \subset S'(T)$ for all $T \to U$. Notation: $S \subset S'$.

Given a collection of sieves $S_ i$, $i \in I$ on $U$ we can define $\bigcup S_ i$ as the sieve with values $(\bigcup S_ i)(T) = \bigcup S_ i(T)$ for all $T \in \mathop{\mathrm{Ob}}\nolimits (\mathcal{C})$. We define the intersection $\bigcap S_ i$ in the same way.

Given $\{ U_ i \to U\} _{i\in I}$ as in the statement, consider the morphisms of presheaves $h_{U_ i} \to h_ U$. We simply define $S$ as the union of the images (Definition 7.3.5) of these maps of presheaves.

The last two statements of the lemma are obvious. $\square$

Definition 7.47.3. Let $\mathcal{C}$ be a category. Given a family of morphisms $\{ f_ i : U_ i \to U\} _{i\in I}$ of $\mathcal{C}$ with target $U$ we say the sieve $S$ on $U$ described in Lemma 7.47.2 part (4) is the sieve on $U$ generated by the morphisms $f_ i$.

Definition 7.47.4. Let $\mathcal{C}$ be a category. Let $f : V \to U$ be a morphism of $\mathcal{C}$. Let $S \subset h_ U$ be a sieve. We define the pullback of $S$ by $f$ to be the sieve $S \times _ U V$ of $V$ defined by the rule

\[ (\alpha : T \to V) \in (S \times _ U V)(T) \Leftrightarrow (f \circ \alpha : T \to U) \in S(T) \]

We leave it to the reader to see that this is indeed a sieve (hint: use Equation 7.47.1.1). We also sometimes call $S \times _ U V$ the base change of $S$ by $f : V \to U$.

Lemma 7.47.5. Let $\mathcal{C}$ be a category. Let $U \in \mathop{\mathrm{Ob}}\nolimits (\mathcal{C})$. Let $S$ be a sieve on $U$. If $f : V \to U$ is in $S$, then $S \times _ U V = h_ V$ is maximal.

Proof. Trivial from the definitions. $\square$

Definition 7.47.6. Let $\mathcal{C}$ be a category. A topology on $\mathcal{C}$ is given by a rule which assigns to every $U \in \mathop{\mathrm{Ob}}\nolimits (\mathcal{C})$ a subset $J(U)$ of the set of all sieves on $U$ satisfying the following conditions

  1. For every morphism $f : V \to U$ in $\mathcal{C}$, and every element $S \in J(U)$ the pullback $S \times _ U V$ is an element of $J(V)$.

  2. If $S$ and $S'$ are sieves on $U \in \mathop{\mathrm{Ob}}\nolimits (\mathcal{C})$, if $S \in J(U)$, and if for all $f \in S(V)$ the pullback $S' \times _ U V$ belongs to $J(V)$, then $S'$ belongs to $J(U)$.

  3. For every $U \in \mathop{\mathrm{Ob}}\nolimits (\mathcal{C})$ the maximal sieve $S = h_ U$ belongs to $J(U)$.

In this case, the sieves belonging to $J(U)$ are called the covering sieves.

Lemma 7.47.7. Let $\mathcal{C}$ be a category. Let $J$ be a topology on $\mathcal{C}$. Let $U \in \mathop{\mathrm{Ob}}\nolimits (\mathcal{C})$.

  1. Finite intersections of elements of $J(U)$ are in $J(U)$.

  2. If $S \in J(U)$ and $S' \supset S$, then $S' \in J(U)$.

Proof. Let $S, S' \in J(U)$. Consider $S'' = S \cap S'$. For every $V \to U$ in $S(U)$ we have

\[ S' \times _ U V = S'' \times _ U V \]

simply because $V \to U$ already is in $S$. Hence by the second axiom of the definition we see that $S'' \in J(U)$.

Let $S \in J(U)$ and $S' \supset S$. For every $V \to U$ in $S(U)$ we have $S' \times _ U V = h_ V$ by Lemma 7.47.5. Thus $S' \times _ U V \in J(V)$ by the third axiom. Hence $S' \in J(U)$ by the second axiom. $\square$

Definition 7.47.8. Let $\mathcal{C}$ be a category. Let $J$, $J'$ be two topologies on $\mathcal{C}$. We say that $J$ is finer or stronger than $J'$ if and only if for every object $U$ of $\mathcal{C}$ we have $J'(U) \subset J(U)$. In this case we also say that $J'$ is coarser or weaker than $J$.

In other words, any covering sieve of $J'$ is a covering sieve of $J$. There exists a finest topology on $\mathcal{C}$, namely that topology where any sieve is a covering sieve. This is called the discrete topology of $\mathcal{C}$. There also exists a coarsest topology. Namely, the topology where $J(U) = \{ h_ U\} $ for all objects $U$. This is called the chaotic or indiscrete topology.

Lemma 7.47.9. Let $\mathcal{C}$ be a category. Let $\{ J_ i\} _{i\in I}$ be a set of topologies.

  1. The rule $J(U) = \bigcap J_ i(U)$ defines a topology on $\mathcal{C}$.

  2. There is a coarsest topology finer than all of the topologies $J_ i$.

Proof. The first part is direct from the definitions. The second follows by taking the intersection of all topologies finer than all of the $J_ i$. $\square$

At this point we can define without any motivation what a sheaf is.

Definition 7.47.10. Let $\mathcal{C}$ be a category endowed with a topology $J$. Let $\mathcal{F}$ be a presheaf of sets on $\mathcal{C}$. We say that $\mathcal{F}$ is a sheaf on $\mathcal{C}$ if for every $U \in \mathop{\mathrm{Ob}}\nolimits (\mathcal{C})$ and for every covering sieve $S$ of $U$ the canonical map

\[ \mathop{\mathrm{Mor}}\nolimits _{\textit{PSh}(\mathcal{C})}(h_ U, \mathcal{F}) \longrightarrow \mathop{\mathrm{Mor}}\nolimits _{\textit{PSh}(\mathcal{C})}(S, \mathcal{F}) \]

is bijective.

Recall that the left hand side of the displayed formula equals $\mathcal{F}(U)$. In other words, $\mathcal{F}$ is a sheaf if and only if a section of $\mathcal{F}$ over $U$ is the same thing as a compatible collection of sections $s_{T, \alpha } \in \mathcal{F}(T)$ parametrized by $(\alpha : T \to U) \in S(T)$, and this for every covering sieve $S$ on $U$.

Lemma 7.47.11. Let $\mathcal{C}$ be a category. Let $\{ \mathcal{F}_ i \} _{i\in I}$ be a collection of presheaves of sets on $\mathcal{C}$. For each $U \in \mathop{\mathrm{Ob}}\nolimits (\mathcal{C})$ denote $J(U)$ the set of sieves $S$ with the following property: For every morphism $V \to U$, the maps

\[ \mathop{\mathrm{Mor}}\nolimits _{\textit{PSh}(\mathcal{C})}(h_ V, \mathcal{F}_ i) \longrightarrow \mathop{\mathrm{Mor}}\nolimits _{\textit{PSh}(\mathcal{C})}(S \times _ U V, \mathcal{F}_ i) \]

are bijective for all $i \in I$. Then $J$ defines a topology on $\mathcal{C}$. This topology is the finest topology in which all of the $\mathcal{F}_ i$ are sheaves.

Proof. If we show that $J$ is a topology, then the last statement of the lemma immediately follows. The first and third axioms of a topology are immediately verified. Thus, assume that we have an object $U$, and sieves $S, S'$ of $U$ such that $S \in J(U)$, and for all $V \to U$ in $S(V)$ we have $S' \times _ U V \in J(V)$. We have to show that $S' \in J(U)$. In other words, we have to show that for any $f : W \to U$, the maps

\[ \mathcal{F}_ i(W) = \mathop{\mathrm{Mor}}\nolimits _{\textit{PSh}(\mathcal{C})}(h_ W, \mathcal{F}_ i) \longrightarrow \mathop{\mathrm{Mor}}\nolimits _{\textit{PSh}(\mathcal{C})}(S' \times _ U W, \mathcal{F}_ i) \]

are bijective for all $i \in I$. Pick an element $i \in I$ and pick an element $\varphi \in \mathop{\mathrm{Mor}}\nolimits _{\textit{PSh}(\mathcal{C})}(S' \times _ U W, \mathcal{F}_ i)$. We will construct a section $s \in \mathcal{F}_ i(W)$ mapping to $\varphi $.

Suppose $\alpha : V \to W$ is an element of $S \times _ U W$. According to the definition of pullbacks we see that the composition $f \circ \alpha : V \to W \to U$ is in $S$. Hence $S' \times _ U V$ is in $J(W)$ by assumption on the pair of sieves $S, S'$. Now we have a commutative diagram of presheaves

\[ \xymatrix{ S' \times _ U V \ar[r] \ar[d] & h_ V \ar[d] \\ S' \times _ U W \ar[r] & h_ W } \]

The restriction of $\varphi $ to $S' \times _ U V$ corresponds to an element $s_{V, \alpha } \in \mathcal{F}_ i(V)$. This we see from the definition of $J$, and because $S' \times _ U V$ is in $J(W)$. We leave it to the reader to check that the rule $(V, \alpha ) \mapsto s_{V, \alpha }$ defines an element $\psi \in \mathop{\mathrm{Mor}}\nolimits _{\textit{PSh}(\mathcal{C})}(S \times _ U W, \mathcal{F}_ i)$. Since $S \in J(U)$ we see immediately from the definition of $J$ that $\psi $ corresponds to an element $s$ of $\mathcal{F}_ i(W)$.

We leave it to the reader to verify that the construction $\varphi \mapsto s$ is inverse to the natural map displayed above. $\square$

Definition 7.47.12. Let $\mathcal{C}$ be a category. The finest topology on $\mathcal{C}$ such that all representable presheaves are sheaves, see Lemma 7.47.11, is called the canonical topology of $\mathcal{C}$.


Comments (0)


Post a comment

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked.

In your comment you can use Markdown and LaTeX style mathematics (enclose it like $\pi$). A preview option is available if you wish to see how it works out (just click on the eye in the toolbar).

Unfortunately JavaScript is disabled in your browser, so the comment preview function will not work.

All contributions are licensed under the GNU Free Documentation License.




In order to prevent bots from posting comments, we would like you to prove that you are human. You can do this by filling in the name of the current tag in the following input field. As a reminder, this is tag 00YW. Beware of the difference between the letter 'O' and the digit '0'.