The Stacks project

59.29 Neighborhoods, stalks and points

We can associate to any geometric point of $S$ a stalk functor which is exact. A map of sheaves on $S_{\acute{e}tale}$ is an isomorphism if and only if it is an isomorphism on all these stalks. A complex of abelian sheaves is exact if and only if the complex of stalks is exact at all geometric points. Altogether this means that the small étale site of a scheme $S$ has enough points. It also turns out that any point of the small étale topos of $S$ (an abstract notion) is given by a geometric point. Thus in some sense the small étale topos of $S$ can be understood in terms of geometric points and neighbourhoods.

Definition 59.29.1. Let $S$ be a scheme.

  1. A geometric point of $S$ is a morphism $\mathop{\mathrm{Spec}}(k) \to S$ where $k$ is algebraically closed. Such a point is usually denoted $\overline{s}$, i.e., by an overlined small case letter. We often use $\overline{s}$ to denote the scheme $\mathop{\mathrm{Spec}}(k)$ as well as the morphism, and we use $\kappa (\overline{s})$ to denote $k$.

  2. We say $\overline{s}$ lies over $s$ to indicate that $s \in S$ is the image of $\overline{s}$.

  3. An étale neighborhood of a geometric point $\overline{s}$ of $S$ is a commutative diagram

    \[ \xymatrix{ & U \ar[d]^\varphi \\ {\overline{s}} \ar[r]^{\overline{s}} \ar[ur]^{\bar u} & S } \]

    where $\varphi $ is an étale morphism of schemes. We write $(U, \overline{u}) \to (S, \overline{s})$.

  4. A morphism of étale neighborhoods $(U, \overline{u}) \to (U', \overline{u}')$ is an $S$-morphism $h: U \to U'$ such that $\overline{u}' = h \circ \overline{u}$.

Remark 59.29.2. Since $U$ and $U'$ are étale over $S$, any $S$-morphism between them is also étale, see Proposition 59.26.2. In particular all morphisms of étale neighborhoods are étale.

Remark 59.29.3. Let $S$ be a scheme and $s \in S$ a point. In More on Morphisms, Definition 37.35.1 we defined the notion of an étale neighbourhood $(U, u) \to (S, s)$ of $(S, s)$. If $\overline{s}$ is a geometric point of $S$ lying over $s$, then any étale neighbourhood $(U, \overline{u}) \to (S, \overline{s})$ gives rise to an étale neighbourhood $(U, u)$ of $(S, s)$ by taking $u \in U$ to be the unique point of $U$ such that $\overline{u}$ lies over $u$. Conversely, given an étale neighbourhood $(U, u)$ of $(S, s)$ the residue field extension $\kappa (u)/\kappa (s)$ is finite separable (see Proposition 59.26.2) and hence we can find an embedding $\kappa (u) \subset \kappa (\overline{s})$ over $\kappa (s)$. In other words, we can find a geometric point $\overline{u}$ of $U$ lying over $u$ such that $(U, \overline{u})$ is an étale neighbourhood of $(S, \overline{s})$. We will use these observations to go between the two types of étale neighbourhoods.

Lemma 59.29.4. Let $S$ be a scheme, and let $\overline{s}$ be a geometric point of $S$. The category of étale neighborhoods is cofiltered. More precisely:

  1. Let $(U_ i, \overline{u}_ i)_{i = 1, 2}$ be two étale neighborhoods of $\overline{s}$ in $S$. Then there exists a third étale neighborhood $(U, \overline{u})$ and morphisms $(U, \overline{u}) \to (U_ i, \overline{u}_ i)$, $i = 1, 2$.

  2. Let $h_1, h_2: (U, \overline{u}) \to (U', \overline{u}')$ be two morphisms between étale neighborhoods of $\overline{s}$. Then there exist an étale neighborhood $(U'', \overline{u}'')$ and a morphism $h : (U'', \overline{u}'') \to (U, \overline{u})$ which equalizes $h_1$ and $h_2$, i.e., such that $h_1 \circ h = h_2 \circ h$.

Proof. For part (1), consider the fibre product $U = U_1 \times _ S U_2$. It is étale over both $U_1$ and $U_2$ because étale morphisms are preserved under base change, see Proposition 59.26.2. The map $\overline{s} \to U$ defined by $(\overline{u}_1, \overline{u}_2)$ gives it the structure of an étale neighborhood mapping to both $U_1$ and $U_2$. For part (2), define $U''$ as the fibre product

\[ \xymatrix{ U'' \ar[r] \ar[d] & U \ar[d]^{(h_1, h_2)} \\ U' \ar[r]^-\Delta & U' \times _ S U'. } \]

Since $\overline{u}$ and $\overline{u}'$ agree over $S$ with $\overline{s}$, we see that $\overline{u}'' = (\overline{u}, \overline{u}')$ is a geometric point of $U''$. In particular $U'' \not= \emptyset $. Moreover, since $U'$ is étale over $S$, so is the fibre product $U'\times _ S U'$ (see Proposition 59.26.2). Hence the vertical arrow $(h_1, h_2)$ is étale by Remark 59.29.2 above. Therefore $U''$ is étale over $U'$ by base change, and hence also étale over $S$ (because compositions of étale morphisms are étale). Thus $(U'', \overline{u}'')$ is a solution to the problem. $\square$

Lemma 59.29.5. Let $S$ be a scheme. Let $\overline{s}$ be a geometric point of $S$. Let $(U, \overline{u})$ be an étale neighborhood of $\overline{s}$. Let $\mathcal{U} = \{ \varphi _ i : U_ i \to U \} _{i\in I}$ be an étale covering. Then there exist $i \in I$ and $\overline{u}_ i : \overline{s} \to U_ i$ such that $\varphi _ i : (U_ i, \overline{u}_ i) \to (U, \overline{u})$ is a morphism of étale neighborhoods.

Proof. As $U = \bigcup _{i\in I} \varphi _ i(U_ i)$, the fibre product $\overline{s} \times _{\overline{u}, U, \varphi _ i} U_ i$ is not empty for some $i$. Then look at the cartesian diagram

\[ \xymatrix{ \overline{s} \times _{\overline{u}, U, \varphi _ i} U_ i \ar[d]^{\text{pr}_1} \ar[r]_-{\text{pr}_2} & U_ i \ar[d]^{\varphi _ i} \\ \mathop{\mathrm{Spec}}(k) = \overline{s} \ar@/^1pc/[u]^\sigma \ar[r]^-{\overline{u}} & U } \]

The projection $\text{pr}_1$ is the base change of an étale morphisms so it is étale, see Proposition 59.26.2. Therefore, $\overline{s} \times _{\overline{u}, U, \varphi _ i} U_ i$ is a disjoint union of finite separable extensions of $k$, by Proposition 59.26.2. Here $\overline{s} = \mathop{\mathrm{Spec}}(k)$. But $k$ is algebraically closed, so all these extensions are trivial, and there exists a section $\sigma $ of $\text{pr}_1$. The composition $\text{pr}_2 \circ \sigma $ gives a map compatible with $\overline{u}$. $\square$

Definition 59.29.6. Let $S$ be a scheme. Let $\mathcal{F}$ be a presheaf on $S_{\acute{e}tale}$. Let $\overline{s}$ be a geometric point of $S$. The stalk of $\mathcal{F}$ at $\overline{s}$ is

\[ \mathcal{F}_{\overline{s}} = \mathop{\mathrm{colim}}\nolimits _{(U, \overline{u})} \mathcal{F}(U) \]

where $(U, \overline{u})$ runs over all étale neighborhoods of $\overline{s}$ in $S$.

By Lemma 59.29.4, this colimit is over a filtered index category, namely the opposite of the category of étale neighbourhoods. In other words, an element of $\mathcal{F}_{\overline{s}}$ can be thought of as a triple $(U, \overline{u}, \sigma )$ where $\sigma \in \mathcal{F}(U)$. Two triples $(U, \overline{u}, \sigma )$, $(U', \overline{u}', \sigma ')$ define the same element of the stalk if there exists a third étale neighbourhood $(U'', \overline{u}'')$ and morphisms of étale neighbourhoods $h : (U'', \overline{u}'') \to (U, \overline{u})$, $h' : (U'', \overline{u}'') \to (U', \overline{u}')$ such that $h^*\sigma = (h')^*\sigma '$ in $\mathcal{F}(U'')$. See Categories, Section 4.19.

Lemma 59.29.7. Let $S$ be a scheme. Let $\overline{s}$ be a geometric point of $S$. Consider the functor

\begin{align*} u : S_{\acute{e}tale}& \longrightarrow \textit{Sets}, \\ U & \longmapsto |U_{\overline{s}}| = \{ \overline{u} \text{ such that }(U, \overline{u}) \text{ is an étale neighbourhood of }\overline{s}\} . \end{align*}

Here $|U_{\overline{s}}|$ denotes the underlying set of the geometric fibre. Then $u$ defines a point $p$ of the site $S_{\acute{e}tale}$ (Sites, Definition 7.32.2) and its associated stalk functor $\mathcal{F} \mapsto \mathcal{F}_ p$ (Sites, Equation 7.32.1.1) is the functor $\mathcal{F} \mapsto \mathcal{F}_{\overline{s}}$ defined above.

Proof. In the proof of Lemma 59.29.5 we have seen that the scheme $U_{\overline{s}}$ is a disjoint union of schemes isomorphic to $\overline{s}$. Thus we can also think of $|U_{\overline{s}}|$ as the set of geometric points of $U$ lying over $\overline{s}$, i.e., as the collection of morphisms $\overline{u} : \overline{s} \to U$ fitting into the diagram of Definition 59.29.1. From this it follows that $u(S)$ is a singleton, and that $u(U \times _ V W) = u(U) \times _{u(V)} u(W)$ whenever $U \to V$ and $W \to V$ are morphisms in $S_{\acute{e}tale}$. And, given a covering $\{ U_ i \to U\} _{i \in I}$ in $S_{\acute{e}tale}$ we see that $\coprod u(U_ i) \to u(U)$ is surjective by Lemma 59.29.5. Hence Sites, Proposition 7.33.3 applies, so $p$ is a point of the site $S_{\acute{e}tale}$. Finally, our functor $\mathcal{F} \mapsto \mathcal{F}_{\overline{s}}$ is given by exactly the same colimit as the functor $\mathcal{F} \mapsto \mathcal{F}_ p$ associated to $p$ in Sites, Equation 7.32.1.1 which proves the final assertion. $\square$

Remark 59.29.8. Let $S$ be a scheme and let $\overline{s} : \mathop{\mathrm{Spec}}(k) \to S$ and $\overline{s}' : \mathop{\mathrm{Spec}}(k') \to S$ be two geometric points of $S$. A morphism $a : \overline{s} \to \overline{s}'$ of geometric points is simply a morphism $a : \mathop{\mathrm{Spec}}(k) \to \mathop{\mathrm{Spec}}(k')$ such that $\overline{s}' \circ a = \overline{s}$. Given such a morphism we obtain a functor from the category of étale neighbourhoods of $\overline{s}'$ to the category of étale neighbourhoods of $\overline{s}$ by the rule $(U, \overline{u}') \mapsto (U, \overline{u}' \circ a)$. Hence we obtain a canonical map

\[ \mathcal{F}_{\overline{s}'} = \mathop{\mathrm{colim}}\nolimits _{(U, \overline{u}')} \mathcal{F}(U) \longrightarrow \mathop{\mathrm{colim}}\nolimits _{(U, \overline{u})} \mathcal{F}(U) = \mathcal{F}_{\overline{s}} \]

from Categories, Lemma 4.14.8. Using the description of elements of stalks as triples this maps the element of $\mathcal{F}_{\overline{s}'}$ represented by the triple $(U, \overline{u}', \sigma )$ to the element of $\mathcal{F}_{\overline{s}}$ represented by the triple $(U, \overline{u}' \circ a, \sigma )$. Since the functor above is clearly an equivalence we conclude that this canonical map is an isomorphism of stalk functors.

Let us make sure we have the map of stalks corresponding to $a$ pointing in the correct direction. Note that the above means, according to Sites, Definition 7.37.2, that $a$ defines a morphism $a : p \to p'$ between the points $p, p'$ of the site $S_{\acute{e}tale}$ associated to $\overline{s}, \overline{s}'$ by Lemma 59.29.7. There are more general morphisms of points (corresponding to specializations of points of $S$) which we will describe later, and which will not be isomorphisms, see Section 59.75.

Lemma 59.29.9. Let $S$ be a scheme. Let $\overline{s}$ be a geometric point of $S$.

  1. The stalk functor $\textit{PAb}(S_{\acute{e}tale}) \to \textit{Ab}$, $\mathcal{F} \mapsto \mathcal{F}_{\overline{s}}$ is exact.

  2. We have $(\mathcal{F}^\# )_{\overline{s}} = \mathcal{F}_{\overline{s}}$ for any presheaf of sets $\mathcal{F}$ on $S_{\acute{e}tale}$.

  3. The functor $\textit{Ab}(S_{\acute{e}tale}) \to \textit{Ab}$, $\mathcal{F} \mapsto \mathcal{F}_{\overline{s}}$ is exact.

  4. Similarly the functors $\textit{PSh}(S_{\acute{e}tale}) \to \textit{Sets}$ and $\mathop{\mathit{Sh}}\nolimits (S_{\acute{e}tale}) \to \textit{Sets}$ given by the stalk functor $\mathcal{F} \mapsto \mathcal{F}_{\overline{x}}$ are exact (see Categories, Definition 4.23.1) and commute with arbitrary colimits.

Proof. Before we indicate how to prove this by direct arguments we note that the result follows from the general material in Modules on Sites, Section 18.36. This is true because $\mathcal{F} \mapsto \mathcal{F}_{\overline{s}}$ comes from a point of the small étale site of $S$, see Lemma 59.29.7. We will only give a direct proof of (1), (2) and (3), and omit a direct proof of (4).

Exactness as a functor on $\textit{PAb}(S_{\acute{e}tale})$ is formal from the fact that directed colimits commute with all colimits and with finite limits. The identification of the stalks in (2) is via the map

\[ \kappa : \mathcal{F}_{\overline{s}} \longrightarrow (\mathcal{F}^\# )_{\overline{s}} \]

induced by the natural morphism $\mathcal{F}\to \mathcal{F}^\# $, see Theorem 59.13.2. We claim that this map is an isomorphism of abelian groups. We will show injectivity and omit the proof of surjectivity.

Let $\sigma \in \mathcal{F}_{\overline{s}}$. There exists an étale neighborhood $(U, \overline{u})\to (S, \overline{s})$ such that $\sigma $ is the image of some section $s \in \mathcal{F}(U)$. If $\kappa (\sigma ) = 0$ in $(\mathcal{F}^\# )_{\overline{s}}$ then there exists a morphism of étale neighborhoods $(U', \overline{u}')\to (U, \overline{u})$ such that $s|_{U'}$ is zero in $\mathcal{F}^\# (U')$. It follows there exists an étale covering $\{ U_ i'\to U'\} _{i\in I}$ such that $s|_{U_ i'}=0$ in $\mathcal{F}(U_ i')$ for all $i$. By Lemma 59.29.5 there exist $i \in I$ and a morphism $\overline{u}_ i': \overline{s} \to U_ i'$ such that $(U_ i', \overline{u}_ i') \to (U', \overline{u}')\to (U, \overline{u})$ are morphisms of étale neighborhoods. Hence $\sigma = 0$ since $(U_ i', \overline{u}_ i') \to (U, \overline{u})$ is a morphism of étale neighbourhoods such that we have $s|_{U'_ i}=0$. This proves $\kappa $ is injective.

To show that the functor $\textit{Ab}(S_{\acute{e}tale}) \to \textit{Ab}$ is exact, consider any short exact sequence in $\textit{Ab}(S_{\acute{e}tale})$: $ 0\to \mathcal{F}\to \mathcal{G}\to \mathcal H \to 0. $ This gives us the exact sequence of presheaves

\[ 0 \to \mathcal{F} \to \mathcal{G} \to \mathcal H \to \mathcal H/^ p\mathcal{G} \to 0, \]

where $/^ p$ denotes the quotient in $\textit{PAb}(S_{\acute{e}tale})$. Taking stalks at $\overline{s}$, we see that $(\mathcal H /^ p\mathcal{G})_{\bar{s}} = (\mathcal H /\mathcal{G})_{\bar{s}} = 0$, since the sheafification of $\mathcal H/^ p\mathcal{G}$ is $0$. Therefore,

\[ 0\to \mathcal{F}_{\overline{s}} \to \mathcal{G}_{\overline{s}} \to \mathcal{H}_{\overline{s}} \to 0 = (\mathcal H/^ p\mathcal{G})_{\overline{s}} \]

is exact, since taking stalks is exact as a functor from presheaves. $\square$

Theorem 59.29.10. Let $S$ be a scheme. A map $a : \mathcal{F} \to \mathcal{G}$ of sheaves of sets is injective (resp. surjective) if and only if the map on stalks $a_{\overline{s}} : \mathcal{F}_{\overline{s}} \to \mathcal{G}_{\overline{s}}$ is injective (resp. surjective) for all geometric points of $S$. A sequence of abelian sheaves on $S_{\acute{e}tale}$ is exact if and only if it is exact on all stalks at geometric points of $S$.

Proof. The necessity of exactness on stalks follows from Lemma 59.29.9. For the converse, it suffices to show that a map of sheaves is surjective (respectively injective) if and only if it is surjective (respectively injective) on all stalks. We prove this in the case of surjectivity, and omit the proof in the case of injectivity.

Let $\alpha : \mathcal{F} \to \mathcal{G}$ be a map of sheaves such that $\mathcal{F}_{\overline{s}} \to \mathcal{G}_{\overline{s}}$ is surjective for all geometric points. Fix $U \in \mathop{\mathrm{Ob}}\nolimits (S_{\acute{e}tale})$ and $s \in \mathcal{G}(U)$. For every $u \in U$ choose some $\overline{u} \to U$ lying over $u$ and an étale neighborhood $(V_ u , \overline{v}_ u) \to (U, \overline{u})$ such that $s|_{V_ u} = \alpha (s_{V_ u})$ for some $s_{V_ u} \in \mathcal{F}(V_ u)$. This is possible since $\alpha $ is surjective on stalks. Then $\{ V_ u \to U\} _{u \in U}$ is an étale covering on which the restrictions of $s$ are in the image of the map $\alpha $. Thus, $\alpha $ is surjective, see Sites, Section 7.11. $\square$

Remarks 59.29.11. On points of the geometric sites.

  1. Theorem 59.29.10 says that the family of points of $S_{\acute{e}tale}$ given by the geometric points of $S$ (Lemma 59.29.7) is conservative, see Sites, Definition 7.38.1. In particular $S_{\acute{e}tale}$ has enough points.

  2. Suppose $\mathcal{F}$ is a sheaf on the big étale site of $S$. Let $T \to S$ be an object of the big étale site of $S$, and let $\overline{t}$ be a geometric point of $T$. Then we define $\mathcal{F}_{\overline{t}}$ as the stalk of the restriction $\mathcal{F}|_{T_{\acute{e}tale}}$ of $\mathcal{F}$ to the small étale site of $T$. In other words, we can define the stalk of $\mathcal{F}$ at any geometric point of any scheme $T/S \in \mathop{\mathrm{Ob}}\nolimits ((\mathit{Sch}/S)_{\acute{e}tale})$.

  3. The big étale site of $S$ also has enough points, by considering all geometric points of all objects of this site, see (2).

The following lemma should be skipped on a first reading.

Lemma 59.29.12. Let $S$ be a scheme.

  1. Let $p$ be a point of the small étale site $S_{\acute{e}tale}$ of $S$ given by a functor $u : S_{\acute{e}tale}\to \textit{Sets}$. Then there exists a geometric point $\overline{s}$ of $S$ such that $p$ is isomorphic to the point of $S_{\acute{e}tale}$ associated to $\overline{s}$ in Lemma 59.29.7.

  2. Let $p : \mathop{\mathit{Sh}}\nolimits (pt) \to \mathop{\mathit{Sh}}\nolimits (S_{\acute{e}tale})$ be a point of the small étale topos of $S$. Then $p$ comes from a geometric point of $S$, i.e., the stalk functor $\mathcal{F} \mapsto \mathcal{F}_ p$ is isomorphic to a stalk functor as defined in Definition 59.29.6.

Proof. By Sites, Lemma 7.32.7 there is a one to one correspondence between points of the site and points of the associated topos, hence it suffices to prove (1). By Sites, Proposition 7.33.3 the functor $u$ has the following properties: (a) $u(S) = \{ *\} $, (b) $u(U \times _ V W) = u(U) \times _{u(V)} u(W)$, and (c) if $\{ U_ i \to U\} $ is an étale covering, then $\coprod u(U_ i) \to u(U)$ is surjective. In particular, if $U' \subset U$ is an open subscheme, then $u(U') \subset u(U)$. Moreover, by Sites, Lemma 7.32.7 we can write $u(U) = p^{-1}(h_ U^\# )$, in other words $u(U)$ is the stalk of the representable sheaf $h_ U$. If $U = V \amalg W$, then we see that $h_ U = (h_ V \amalg h_ W)^\# $ and we get $u(U) = u(V) \amalg u(W)$ since $p^{-1}$ is exact.

Consider the restriction of $u$ to $S_{Zar}$. By Sites, Examples 7.33.5 and 7.33.6 there exists a unique point $s \in S$ such that for $S' \subset S$ open we have $u(S') = \{ *\} $ if $s \in S'$ and $u(S') = \emptyset $ if $s \not\in S'$. Note that if $\varphi : U \to S$ is an object of $S_{\acute{e}tale}$ then $\varphi (U) \subset S$ is open (see Proposition 59.26.2) and $\{ U \to \varphi (U)\} $ is an étale covering. Hence we conclude that $u(U) = \emptyset \Leftrightarrow s \in \varphi (U)$.

Pick a geometric point $\overline{s} : \overline{s} \to S$ lying over $s$, see Definition 59.29.1 for customary abuse of notation. Suppose that $\varphi : U \to S$ is an object of $S_{\acute{e}tale}$ with $U$ affine. Note that $\varphi $ is separated, and that the fibre $U_ s$ of $\varphi $ over $s$ is an affine scheme over $\mathop{\mathrm{Spec}}(\kappa (s))$ which is the spectrum of a finite product of finite separable extensions $k_ i$ of $\kappa (s)$. Hence we may apply Étale Morphisms, Lemma 41.18.2 to get an étale neighbourhood $(V, \overline{v})$ of $(S, \overline{s})$ such that

\[ U \times _ S V = U_1 \amalg \ldots \amalg U_ n \amalg W \]

with $U_ i \to V$ an isomorphism and $W$ having no point lying over $\overline{v}$. Thus we conclude that

\[ u(U) \times u(V) = u(U \times _ S V) = u(U_1) \amalg \ldots \amalg u(U_ n) \amalg u(W) \]

and of course also $u(U_ i) = u(V)$. After shrinking $V$ a bit we can assume that $V$ has exactly one point lying over $s$, and hence $W$ has no point lying over $s$. By the above this then gives $u(W) = \emptyset $. Hence we obtain

\[ u(U) \times u(V) = u(U_1) \amalg \ldots \amalg u(U_ n) = \coprod \nolimits _{i = 1, \ldots , n} u(V) \]

Note that $u(V) \not= \emptyset $ as $s$ is in the image of $V \to S$. In particular, we see that in this situation $u(U)$ is a finite set with $n$ elements.

Consider the limit

\[ \mathop{\mathrm{lim}}\nolimits _{(V, \overline{v})} u(V) \]

over the category of étale neighbourhoods $(V, \overline{v})$ of $\overline{s}$. It is clear that we get the same value when taking the limit over the subcategory of $(V, \overline{v})$ with $V$ affine. By the previous paragraph (applied with the roles of $V$ and $U$ switched) we see that in this case $u(V)$ is always a finite nonempty set. Moreover, the limit is cofiltered, see Lemma 59.29.4. Hence by Categories, Section 4.20 the limit is nonempty. Pick an element $x$ from this limit. This means we obtain a $x_{V, \overline{v}} \in u(V)$ for every étale neighbourhood $(V, \overline{v})$ of $(S, \overline{s})$ such that for every morphism of étale neighbourhoods $\varphi : (V', \overline{v}') \to (V, \overline{v})$ we have $u(\varphi )(x_{V', \overline{v}'}) = x_{V, \overline{v}}$.

We will use the choice of $x$ to construct a functorial bijective map

\[ c : |U_{\overline{s}}| \longrightarrow u(U) \]

for $U \in \mathop{\mathrm{Ob}}\nolimits (S_{\acute{e}tale})$ which will conclude the proof. See Lemma 59.29.7 and its proof for a description of $|U_{\overline{s}}|$. First we claim that it suffices to construct the map for $U$ affine. We omit the proof of this claim. Assume $U \to S$ in $S_{\acute{e}tale}$ with $U$ affine, and let $\overline{u} : \overline{s} \to U$ be an element of $|U_{\overline{s}}|$. Choose a $(V, \overline{v})$ such that $U \times _ S V$ decomposes as in the third paragraph of the proof. Then the pair $(\overline{u}, \overline{v})$ gives a geometric point of $U \times _ S V$ lying over $\overline{v}$ and determines one of the components $U_ i$ of $U \times _ S V$. More precisely, there exists a section $\sigma : V \to U \times _ S V$ of the projection $\text{pr}_ U$ such that $(\overline{u}, \overline{v}) = \sigma \circ \overline{v}$. Set $c(\overline{u}) = u(\text{pr}_ U)(u(\sigma )(x_{V, \overline{v}})) \in u(U)$. We have to check this is independent of the choice of $(V, \overline{v})$. By Lemma 59.29.4 the category of étale neighbourhoods is cofiltered. Hence it suffice to show that given a morphism of étale neighbourhood $\varphi : (V', \overline{v}') \to (V, \overline{v})$ and a choice of a section $\sigma ' : V' \to U \times _ S V'$ of the projection such that $(\overline{u}, \overline{v'}) = \sigma ' \circ \overline{v}'$ we have $u(\sigma ')(x_{V', \overline{v}'}) = u(\sigma )(x_{V, \overline{v}})$. Consider the diagram

\[ \xymatrix{ V' \ar[d]^{\sigma '} \ar[r]_\varphi & V \ar[d]^\sigma \\ U \times _ S V' \ar[r]^{1 \times \varphi } & U \times _ S V } \]

Now, it may not be the case that this diagram commutes. The reason is that the schemes $V'$ and $V$ may not be connected, and hence the decompositions used to construct $\sigma '$ and $\sigma $ above may not be unique. But we do know that $\sigma \circ \varphi \circ \overline{v}' = (1 \times \varphi ) \circ \sigma ' \circ \overline{v}'$ by construction. Hence, since $U \times _ S V$ is étale over $S$, there exists an open neighbourhood $V'' \subset V'$ of $\overline{v'}$ such that the diagram does commute when restricted to $V''$, see Morphisms, Lemma 29.35.17. This means we may extend the diagram above to

\[ \xymatrix{ V'' \ar[r] \ar[d]^{\sigma '|_{V''}} & V' \ar[d]^{\sigma '} \ar[r]_\varphi & V \ar[d]^\sigma \\ U \times _ S V'' \ar[r] & U \times _ S V' \ar[r]^{1 \times \varphi } & U \times _ S V } \]

such that the left square and the outer rectangle commute. Since $u$ is a functor this implies that $x_{V'', \overline{v}'}$ maps to the same element in $u(U \times _ S V)$ no matter which route we take through the diagram. On the other hand, it maps to the elements $x_{V', \overline{v}'}$ and $x_{V, \overline{v}}$ in $u(V')$ and $u(V)$. This implies the desired equality $u(\sigma ')(x_{V', \overline{v}'}) = u(\sigma )(x_{V, \overline{v}})$.

In a similar manner one proves that the construction $c : |U_{\overline{s}}| \to u(U)$ is functorial in $U$; details omitted. And finally, by the results of the third paragraph it is clear that the map $c$ is bijective which ends the proof of the lemma. $\square$


Comments (3)

Comment #407 by Rex on

The assumption here that a geometric point be algebraically closed differs from the definition in SGA 4.5, where it is only required to be separably closed. Does this difference affect how the theory is set up?

Comment #409 by on

Yes, when I was writing this I sort of hesitated. First of all, there is no difference in the theory for \'etale sheaves, stalks, etc. This is true because every field has an absolutely canonical perfect closure and the perfect closure of a separably closed field is algebraically closed. Moreover, if we have with separably closed and associated perfect closure , then given \'etale there there is a bijection between lifts of to and lifts of to . This is true because the residue field extensions induced by the etale morphism are finite separable.

The real reason for using geometric points as we do here, is that in most algebraic geometry texts one uses algebraically closed fields to define geometric points.

Comment #4089 by Tongmu on

Typo: in the proof of lemma 04HU, the last sentence of the second paragragh, it should be .


Post a comment

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked.

In your comment you can use Markdown and LaTeX style mathematics (enclose it like $\pi$). A preview option is available if you wish to see how it works out (just click on the eye in the toolbar).

Unfortunately JavaScript is disabled in your browser, so the comment preview function will not work.

All contributions are licensed under the GNU Free Documentation License.




In order to prevent bots from posting comments, we would like you to prove that you are human. You can do this by filling in the name of the current tag in the following input field. As a reminder, this is tag 03PN. Beware of the difference between the letter 'O' and the digit '0'.