Definition 59.13.1. Let \mathcal{F} be a presheaf on the site \mathcal{C} and \mathcal{U} = \{ U_ i \to U\} \in \text{Cov} (\mathcal{C}). We define the zeroth Čech cohomology group of \mathcal{F} with respect to \mathcal{U} by
59.13 Sheafification
There is a canonical map \mathcal{F}(U) \to \check H^0 (\mathcal{U}, \mathcal{F}), s \mapsto (s |_{U_ i})_{i\in I}. We say that a morphism of coverings from a covering \mathcal{V} = \{ V_ j \to V\} _{j \in J} to \mathcal{U} is a triple (\chi , \alpha , \chi _ j), where \chi : V \to U is a morphism, \alpha : J \to I is a map of sets, and for all j \in J the morphism \chi _ j fits into a commutative diagram
Given the data \chi , \alpha , \{ \chi _ j\} _{j \in J} we define
We then claim that
the map is well-defined, and
depends only on \chi and is independent of the choice of \alpha , \{ \chi _ j\} _{j \in J}.
We omit the proof of the first fact. To see part (2), consider another triple (\psi , \beta , \psi _ j) with \chi = \psi . Then we have the commutative diagram
Given a section s \in \mathcal{F}(\mathcal{U}), its image in \mathcal{F}(V_ j) under the map given by (\chi , \alpha , \{ \chi _ j\} _{j \in J}) is \chi _ j^*s_{\alpha (j)}, and its image under the map given by (\psi , \beta , \{ \psi _ j\} _{j \in J}) is \psi _ j^*s_{\beta (j)}. These two are equal since by assumption s \in \check H^0(\mathcal{U}, \mathcal{F}) and hence both are equal to the pullback of the common value
pulled back by the map (\chi _ j, \psi _ j) in the diagram.
Theorem 59.13.2. Let \mathcal{C} be a site and \mathcal{F} a presheaf on \mathcal{C}.
The rule
U \mapsto \mathcal{F}^+(U) := \mathop{\mathrm{colim}}\nolimits _{\mathcal{U} \text{ covering of }U} \check H^0(\mathcal{U}, \mathcal{F})is a presheaf. And the colimit is a directed one.
There is a canonical map of presheaves \mathcal{F} \to \mathcal{F}^+.
If \mathcal{F} is a separated presheaf then \mathcal{F}^+ is a sheaf and the map in (2) is injective.
\mathcal{F}^+ is a separated presheaf.
\mathcal{F}^\# = (\mathcal{F}^+)^+ is a sheaf, and the canonical map induces a functorial isomorphism
\mathop{\mathrm{Hom}}\nolimits _{\textit{PSh}(\mathcal{C})}(\mathcal{F}, \mathcal{G}) = \mathop{\mathrm{Hom}}\nolimits _{\mathop{\mathit{Sh}}\nolimits (\mathcal{C})}(\mathcal{F}^\# , \mathcal{G})for any \mathcal{G} \in \mathop{\mathit{Sh}}\nolimits (\mathcal{C}).
Proof. See Sites, Theorem 7.10.10. \square
In other words, this means that the natural map \mathcal{F} \to \mathcal{F}^\# is a left adjoint to the forgetful functor \mathop{\mathit{Sh}}\nolimits (\mathcal{C}) \to \textit{PSh}(\mathcal{C}).
Comments (7)
Comment #236 by Keenan Kidwell on
Comment #242 by Johan on
Comment #2810 by Dario Weißmann on
Comment #2811 by Dario Weißmann on
Comment #2912 by Johan on
Comment #6614 by Liu S-H on
Comment #6855 by Johan on