The Stacks project

Lemma 58.3.7. Let $(\mathcal{C}, F)$ be a Galois category. Let $X \to Y \in \text{Arrows}(\mathcal{C})$. Then

  1. $F$ is faithful,

  2. $X \to Y$ is a monomorphism $\Leftrightarrow F(X) \to F(Y)$ is injective,

  3. $X \to Y$ is an epimorphism $\Leftrightarrow F(X) \to F(Y)$ is surjective,

  4. an object $A$ of $\mathcal{C}$ is initial if and only if $F(A) = \emptyset $,

  5. an object $Z$ of $\mathcal{C}$ is final if and only if $F(Z)$ is a singleton,

  6. if $X$ and $Y$ are connected, then $X \to Y$ is an epimorphism,

  7. if $X$ is connected and $a, b : X \to Y$ are two morphisms then $a = b$ as soon as $F(a)$ and $F(b)$ agree on one element of $F(X)$,

  8. if $X = \coprod _{i = 1, \ldots , n} X_ i$ and $Y = \coprod _{j = 1, \ldots , m} Y_ j$ where $X_ i$, $Y_ j$ are connected, then there is map $\alpha : \{ 1, \ldots , n\} \to \{ 1, \ldots , m\} $ such that $X \to Y$ comes from a collection of morphisms $X_ i \to Y_{\alpha (i)}$.

Proof. Proof of (1). Suppose $a, b : X \to Y$ with $F(a) = F(b)$. Let $E$ be the equalizer of $a$ and $b$. Then $F(E) = F(X)$ and we see that $E = X$ because $F$ reflects isomorphisms.

Proof of (2). This is true because $F$ turns the morphism $X \to X \times _ Y X$ into the map $F(X) \to F(X) \times _{F(Y)} F(X)$ and $F$ reflects isomorphisms.

Proof of (3). This is true because $F$ turns the morphism $Y \amalg _ X Y \to Y$ into the map $F(Y) \amalg _{F(X)} F(Y) \to F(Y)$ and $F$ reflects isomorphisms.

Proof of (4). There exists an initial object $A$ and certainly $F(A) = \emptyset $. On the other hand, if $X$ is an object with $F(X) = \emptyset $, then the unique map $A \to X$ induces a bijection $F(A) \to F(X)$ and hence $A \to X$ is an isomorphism.

Proof of (5). There exists a final object $Z$ and certainly $F(Z)$ is a singleton. On the other hand, if $X$ is an object with $F(X)$ a singleton, then the unique map $X \to Z$ induces a bijection $F(X) \to F(Z)$ and hence $X \to Z$ is an isomorphism.

Proof of (6). The equalizer $E$ of the two maps $Y \to Y \amalg _ X Y$ is not an initial object of $\mathcal{C}$ because $X \to Y$ factors through $E$ and $F(X) \not= \emptyset $. Hence $E = Y$ and we conclude.

Proof of (7). The equalizer $E$ of $a$ and $b$ comes with a monomorphism $E \to X$ and $F(E) \subset F(X)$ is the set of elements where $F(a)$ and $F(b)$ agree. To finish use that either $E$ is initial or $E = X$.

Proof of (8). For each $i, j$ we see that $E_{ij} = X_ i \times _ Y Y_ j$ is either initial or equal to $X_ i$. Picking $s \in F(X_ i)$ we see that $E_{ij} = X_ i$ if and only if $s$ maps to an element of $F(Y_ j) \subset F(Y)$, hence this happens for a unique $j = \alpha (i)$. $\square$


Comments (0)

There are also:

  • 7 comment(s) on Section 58.3: Galois categories

Post a comment

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked.

In your comment you can use Markdown and LaTeX style mathematics (enclose it like $\pi$). A preview option is available if you wish to see how it works out (just click on the eye in the toolbar).

Unfortunately JavaScript is disabled in your browser, so the comment preview function will not work.

All contributions are licensed under the GNU Free Documentation License.




In order to prevent bots from posting comments, we would like you to prove that you are human. You can do this by filling in the name of the current tag in the following input field. As a reminder, this is tag 0BN0. Beware of the difference between the letter 'O' and the digit '0'.