Lemma 14.17.4. Assume the category \mathcal{C} has coproducts of any two objects and finite limits. Let U be a simplicial set, with U_ n finite nonempty for all n \geq 0. Assume that all n-simplices of U are degenerate for all n \gg 0. Let V be a simplicial object of \mathcal{C}. Then \mathop{\mathrm{Hom}}\nolimits (U, V) exists, moreover we have the expected equalities
Proof. We construct this simplicial object as follows. For n \geq 0 let \mathop{\mathrm{Hom}}\nolimits (U, V)_ n denote the object of \mathcal{C} representing the functor
This exists by Lemma 14.17.3 because U \times \Delta [n] is a simplicial set with finite sets of simplices and no nondegenerate simplices in high enough degree, see Lemma 14.11.5. For \varphi : [m] \to [n] we obtain an induced map of simplicial sets \varphi : \Delta [m] \to \Delta [n]. Hence we obtain a morphism X \times U \times \Delta [m] \to X \times U \times \Delta [n] functorial in X, and hence a transformation of functors, which in turn gives
Clearly this defines a contravariant functor \mathop{\mathrm{Hom}}\nolimits (U, V) from \Delta into the category \mathcal{C}. In other words, we have a simplicial object of \mathcal{C}.
We have to show that \mathop{\mathrm{Hom}}\nolimits (U, V) satisfies the desired universal property
To see this, let f : W \to \mathop{\mathrm{Hom}}\nolimits (U, V) be given. We want to construct the element f' : W \times U \to V of the right hand side. By construction, each f_ n : W_ n \to \mathop{\mathrm{Hom}}\nolimits (U, V)_ n corresponds to a morphism f_ n : W_ n \times U \times \Delta [n] \to V. Further, for every morphism \varphi : [m] \to [n] the diagram
is commutative. For \psi : [n] \to [k] in (\Delta [n])_ k we denote (f_ n)_{k, \psi } : W_ n \times U_ k \to V_ k the component of (f_ n)_ k corresponding to the element \psi . We define f'_ n : W_ n \times U_ n \to V_ n as f'_ n = (f_ n)_{n, \text{id}}, in other words, as the restriction of (f_ n)_ n : W_ n \times U_ n \times (\Delta [n])_ n \to V_ n to W_ n \times U_ n \times \text{id}_{[n]}. To see that the collection (f'_ n) defines a morphism of simplicial objects, we have to show for any \varphi : [m] \to [n] that V(\varphi ) \circ f'_ n = f'_ m \circ W(\varphi ) \times U(\varphi ). The commutative diagram above says that (f_ n)_{m, \varphi } : W_ n \times U_ m \to V_ m is equal to (f_ m)_{m, \text{id}} \circ W(\varphi ) : W_ n \times U_ m \to V_ m. But then the fact that f_ n is a morphism of simplicial objects implies that the diagram
is commutative. And this implies that (f_ n)_{m, \varphi } \circ U(\varphi ) is equal to V(\varphi ) \circ (f_ n)_{n, \text{id}}. Altogether we obtain V(\varphi ) \circ (f_ n)_{n, \text{id}} = (f_ n)_{m, \varphi } \circ U(\varphi ) = (f_ m)_{m, \text{id}} \circ W(\varphi )\circ U(\varphi ) = (f_ m)_{m, \text{id}} \circ W(\varphi )\times U(\varphi ) as desired.
On the other hand, given a morphism f' : W \times U \to V we define a morphism f : W \to \mathop{\mathrm{Hom}}\nolimits (U, V) as follows. By Lemma 14.13.4 the morphisms \text{id} : W_ n \to W_ n corresponds to a unique morphism c_ n : W_ n \times \Delta [n] \to W. Hence we can consider the composition
By construction this corresponds to a unique morphism f_ n : W_ n \to \mathop{\mathrm{Hom}}\nolimits (U, V)_ n. We leave it to the reader to see that these define a morphism of simplicial sets as desired.
We also leave it to the reader to see that f \mapsto f' and f' \mapsto f are mutually inverse operations. \square
Comments (0)