29.50 Birational morphisms
You may be used to the notion of a birational map of varieties having the property that it is an isomorphism over an open subset of the target. However, in general a birational morphism may not be an isomorphism over any nonempty open, see Example 29.50.4. Here is the formal definition.
reference
Definition 29.50.1. Let X, Y be schemes. Assume X and Y have finitely many irreducible components. We say a morphism f : X \to Y is birational if
f induces a bijection between the set of generic points of irreducible components of X and the set of generic points of the irreducible components of Y, and
for every generic point \eta \in X of an irreducible component of X the local ring map \mathcal{O}_{Y, f(\eta )} \to \mathcal{O}_{X, \eta } is an isomorphism.
We will see below that the fibres of a birational morphism over generic points are singletons. Moreover, we will see that in most cases one encounters in practice the existence a birational morphism between irreducible schemes X and Y implies X and Y are birational schemes.
Lemma 29.50.2. Let f : X \to Y be a morphism of schemes having finitely many irreducible components. If f is birational then f is dominant.
Proof.
Follows from Lemma 29.8.2 and the definition.
\square
Lemma 29.50.3. Let f : X \to Y be a birational morphism of schemes having finitely many irreducible components. If y \in Y is the generic point of an irreducible component, then the base change X \times _ Y \mathop{\mathrm{Spec}}(\mathcal{O}_{Y, y}) \to \mathop{\mathrm{Spec}}(\mathcal{O}_{Y, y}) is an isomorphism.
Proof.
We may assume Y = \mathop{\mathrm{Spec}}(B) is affine and irreducible. Then X is irreducible too. If we prove the result for any nonempty affine open U \subset X, then the result holds for X (small argument omitted). Hence we may assume X is affine too, say X = \mathop{\mathrm{Spec}}(A). Let y \in Y correspond to the minimal prime \mathfrak q \subset B. By assumption A has a unique minimal prime \mathfrak p lying over \mathfrak q and B_\mathfrak q \to A_\mathfrak p is an isomorphism. It follows that A_\mathfrak q \to \kappa (\mathfrak p) is surjective, hence \mathfrak p A_\mathfrak q is a maximal ideal. On the other hand \mathfrak p A_\mathfrak q is the unique minimal prime of A_\mathfrak q. We conclude that \mathfrak p A_\mathfrak q is the unique prime of A_\mathfrak q and that A_\mathfrak q = A_\mathfrak p. Since A_\mathfrak q = A \otimes _ B B_\mathfrak q the lemma follows.
\square
Example 29.50.4. Here are two examples of birational morphisms which are not isomorphisms over any open of the target.
First example. Let k be an infinite field. Let A = k[x]. Let B = k[x, \{ y_{\alpha }\} _{\alpha \in k}]/ ((x-\alpha )y_\alpha , y_\alpha y_\beta ). There is an inclusion A \subset B and a retraction B \to A setting all y_\alpha equal to zero. Both the morphism \mathop{\mathrm{Spec}}(A) \to \mathop{\mathrm{Spec}}(B) and the morphism \mathop{\mathrm{Spec}}(B) \to \mathop{\mathrm{Spec}}(A) are birational but not an isomorphism over any open.
Second example. Let A be a domain. Let S \subset A be a multiplicative subset not containing 0. With B = S^{-1}A the morphism f : \mathop{\mathrm{Spec}}(B) \to \mathop{\mathrm{Spec}}(A) is birational. If there exists an open U of \mathop{\mathrm{Spec}}(A) such that f^{-1}(U) \to U is an isomorphism, then there exists an a \in A such that each every element of S becomes invertible in the principal localization A_ a. Taking A = \mathbf{Z} and S the set of odd integers give a counter example.
Lemma 29.50.5. Let f : X \to Y be a birational morphism of schemes having finitely many irreducible components over a base scheme S. Assume one of the following conditions is satisfied
f is locally of finite type and Y reduced,
f is locally of finite presentation.
Then there exist dense opens U \subset X and V \subset Y such that f(U) \subset V and f|_ U : U \to V is an isomorphism. In particular if X and Y are irreducible, then X and Y are S-birational.
Proof.
There is an immediate reduction to the case where X and Y are irreducible which we omit. Moreover, after shrinking further and we may assume X and Y are affine, say X = \mathop{\mathrm{Spec}}(A) and Y = \mathop{\mathrm{Spec}}(B). By assumption A, resp. B has a unique minimal prime \mathfrak p, resp. \mathfrak q, the prime \mathfrak p lies over \mathfrak q, and B_\mathfrak q = A_\mathfrak p. By Lemma 29.50.3 we have B_\mathfrak q = A_\mathfrak q = A_\mathfrak p.
Suppose B \to A is of finite type, say A = B[x_1, \ldots , x_ n]. There exist a b_ i \in B and g_ i \in B \setminus \mathfrak q such that b_ i/g_ i maps to the image of x_ i in A_\mathfrak q. Hence b_ i - g_ ix_ i maps to zero in A_{g_ i'} for some g_ i' \in B \setminus \mathfrak q. Setting g = \prod g_ i g'_ i we see that B_ g \to A_ g is surjective. If moreover Y is reduced, then the map B_ g \to B_\mathfrak q is injective and hence B_ g \to A_ g is injective as well. This proves case (1).
Proof of (2). By the argument given in the previous paragraph we may assume that B \to A is surjective. As f is locally of finite presentation the kernel J \subset B is a finitely generated ideal. Say J = (b_1, \ldots , b_ r). Since B_\mathfrak q = A_\mathfrak q there exist g_ i \in B \setminus \mathfrak q such that g_ i b_ i = 0. Setting g = \prod g_ i we see that B_ g \to A_ g is an isomorphism.
\square
Lemma 29.50.6. Let S be a scheme. Let X and Y be irreducible schemes locally of finite presentation over S. Let x \in X and y \in Y be the generic points. The following are equivalent
X and Y are S-birational,
there exist nonempty opens of X and Y which are S-isomorphic, and
x and y map to the same point s of S and \mathcal{O}_{X, x} and \mathcal{O}_{Y, y} are isomorphic as \mathcal{O}_{S, s}-algebras.
Proof.
We have seen the equivalence of (1) and (2) in Lemma 29.49.12. It is immediate that (2) implies (3). To finish we assume (3) holds and we prove (1). By Lemma 29.49.2 there is a rational map f : U \to Y which sends x \in U to y and induces the given isomorphism \mathcal{O}_{Y, y} \cong \mathcal{O}_{X, x}. Thus f is a birational morphism and hence induces an isomorphism on nonempty opens by Lemma 29.50.5. This finishes the proof.
\square
Lemma 29.50.7. Let S be a scheme. Let X and Y be integral schemes locally of finite type over S. Let x \in X and y \in Y be the generic points. The following are equivalent
X and Y are S-birational,
there exist nonempty opens of X and Y which are S-isomorphic, and
x and y map to the same point s \in S and \kappa (x) \cong \kappa (y) as \kappa (s)-extensions.
Proof.
We have seen the equivalence of (1) and (2) in Lemma 29.49.12. It is immediate that (2) implies (3). To finish we assume (3) holds and we prove (1). Observe that \mathcal{O}_{X, x} = \kappa (x) and \mathcal{O}_{Y, y} = \kappa (y) by Algebra, Lemma 10.25.1. By Lemma 29.49.2 there is a rational map f : U \to Y which sends x \in U to y and induces the given isomorphism \mathcal{O}_{Y, y} \cong \mathcal{O}_{X, x}. Thus f is a birational morphism and hence induces an isomorphism on nonempty opens by Lemma 29.50.5. This finishes the proof.
\square
Comments (2)
Comment #9757 by Fanjun Meng on
Comment #9758 by Laurent Moret-Bailly on