Lemma 4.18.1. Let \mathcal{I} be a category with
\mathop{\mathrm{Ob}}\nolimits (\mathcal{I}) is finite, and
there exist finitely many morphisms f_1, \ldots , f_ m \in \text{Arrows}(\mathcal{I}) such that every morphism of \mathcal{I} is a composition f_{j_1} \circ f_{j_2} \circ \ldots \circ f_{j_ k}.
Then there exists a functor F : \mathcal{J} \to \mathcal{I} such that
\mathcal{J} is a finite category, and
for any diagram M : \mathcal{I} \to \mathcal{C} the (co)limit of M over \mathcal{I} exists if and only if the (co)limit of M \circ F over \mathcal{J} exists and in this case the (co)limits are canonically isomorphic.
Moreover, \mathcal{J} is connected (resp. nonempty) if and only if \mathcal{I} is so.
Proof.
Say \mathop{\mathrm{Ob}}\nolimits (\mathcal{I}) = \{ x_1, \ldots , x_ n\} . Denote s, t : \{ 1, \ldots , m\} \to \{ 1, \ldots , n\} the functions such that f_ j : x_{s(j)} \to x_{t(j)}. We set \mathop{\mathrm{Ob}}\nolimits (\mathcal{J}) = \{ y_1, \ldots , y_ n, z_1, \ldots , z_ n\} Besides the identity morphisms we introduce morphisms g_ j : y_{s(j)} \to z_{t(j)}, j = 1, \ldots , m and morphisms h_ i : y_ i \to z_ i, i = 1, \ldots , n. Since all of the nonidentity morphisms in \mathcal{J} go from a y to a z there are no compositions to define and no associativities to check. Set F(y_ i) = F(z_ i) = x_ i. Set F(g_ j) = f_ j and F(h_ i) = \text{id}_{x_ i}. It is clear that F is a functor. It is clear that \mathcal{J} is finite. It is clear that \mathcal{J} is connected, resp. nonempty if and only if \mathcal{I} is so.
Let M : \mathcal{I} \to \mathcal{C} be a diagram. Consider an object W of \mathcal{C} and morphisms q_ i : W \to M(x_ i) as in Definition 4.14.1. Then by taking q_ i : W \to M(F(y_ i)) = M(F(z_ i)) = M(x_ i) we obtain a family of maps as in Definition 4.14.1 for the diagram M \circ F. Conversely, suppose we are given maps qy_ i : W \to M(F(y_ i)) and qz_ i : W \to M(F(z_ i)) as in Definition 4.14.1 for the diagram M \circ F. Since
M(F(h_ i)) = \text{id} : M(F(y_ i)) = M(x_ i) \longrightarrow M(x_ i) = M(F(z_ i))
we conclude that qy_ i = qz_ i for all i. Set q_ i equal to this common value. The compatibility of q_{s(j)} = qy_{s(j)} and q_{t(j)} = qz_{t(j)} with the morphism M(f_ j) guarantees that the family q_ i is compatible with all morphisms in \mathcal{I} as by assumption every such morphism is a composition of the morphisms f_ j. Thus we have found a canonical bijection
\mathop{\mathrm{lim}}\nolimits _{B \in \mathop{\mathrm{Ob}}\nolimits (\mathcal{J})} \mathop{\mathrm{Mor}}\nolimits _\mathcal {C}(W, M(F(B))) = \mathop{\mathrm{lim}}\nolimits _{A \in \mathop{\mathrm{Ob}}\nolimits (\mathcal{I})} \mathop{\mathrm{Mor}}\nolimits _\mathcal {C}(W, M(A))
which implies the statement on limits in the lemma. The statement on colimits is proved in the same way (proof omitted).
\square
Comments (0)
There are also: