Processing math: 100%

The Stacks project

Lemma 4.18.1. Let \mathcal{I} be a category with

  1. \mathop{\mathrm{Ob}}\nolimits (\mathcal{I}) is finite, and

  2. there exist finitely many morphisms f_1, \ldots , f_ m \in \text{Arrows}(\mathcal{I}) such that every morphism of \mathcal{I} is a composition f_{j_1} \circ f_{j_2} \circ \ldots \circ f_{j_ k}.

Then there exists a functor F : \mathcal{J} \to \mathcal{I} such that

  1. \mathcal{J} is a finite category, and

  2. for any diagram M : \mathcal{I} \to \mathcal{C} the (co)limit of M over \mathcal{I} exists if and only if the (co)limit of M \circ F over \mathcal{J} exists and in this case the (co)limits are canonically isomorphic.

Moreover, \mathcal{J} is connected (resp. nonempty) if and only if \mathcal{I} is so.

Proof. Say \mathop{\mathrm{Ob}}\nolimits (\mathcal{I}) = \{ x_1, \ldots , x_ n\} . Denote s, t : \{ 1, \ldots , m\} \to \{ 1, \ldots , n\} the functions such that f_ j : x_{s(j)} \to x_{t(j)}. We set \mathop{\mathrm{Ob}}\nolimits (\mathcal{J}) = \{ y_1, \ldots , y_ n, z_1, \ldots , z_ n\} Besides the identity morphisms we introduce morphisms g_ j : y_{s(j)} \to z_{t(j)}, j = 1, \ldots , m and morphisms h_ i : y_ i \to z_ i, i = 1, \ldots , n. Since all of the nonidentity morphisms in \mathcal{J} go from a y to a z there are no compositions to define and no associativities to check. Set F(y_ i) = F(z_ i) = x_ i. Set F(g_ j) = f_ j and F(h_ i) = \text{id}_{x_ i}. It is clear that F is a functor. It is clear that \mathcal{J} is finite. It is clear that \mathcal{J} is connected, resp. nonempty if and only if \mathcal{I} is so.

Let M : \mathcal{I} \to \mathcal{C} be a diagram. Consider an object W of \mathcal{C} and morphisms q_ i : W \to M(x_ i) as in Definition 4.14.1. Then by taking q_ i : W \to M(F(y_ i)) = M(F(z_ i)) = M(x_ i) we obtain a family of maps as in Definition 4.14.1 for the diagram M \circ F. Conversely, suppose we are given maps qy_ i : W \to M(F(y_ i)) and qz_ i : W \to M(F(z_ i)) as in Definition 4.14.1 for the diagram M \circ F. Since

M(F(h_ i)) = \text{id} : M(F(y_ i)) = M(x_ i) \longrightarrow M(x_ i) = M(F(z_ i))

we conclude that qy_ i = qz_ i for all i. Set q_ i equal to this common value. The compatibility of q_{s(j)} = qy_{s(j)} and q_{t(j)} = qz_{t(j)} with the morphism M(f_ j) guarantees that the family q_ i is compatible with all morphisms in \mathcal{I} as by assumption every such morphism is a composition of the morphisms f_ j. Thus we have found a canonical bijection

\mathop{\mathrm{lim}}\nolimits _{B \in \mathop{\mathrm{Ob}}\nolimits (\mathcal{J})} \mathop{\mathrm{Mor}}\nolimits _\mathcal {C}(W, M(F(B))) = \mathop{\mathrm{lim}}\nolimits _{A \in \mathop{\mathrm{Ob}}\nolimits (\mathcal{I})} \mathop{\mathrm{Mor}}\nolimits _\mathcal {C}(W, M(A))

which implies the statement on limits in the lemma. The statement on colimits is proved in the same way (proof omitted). \square


Comments (0)

There are also:

  • 3 comment(s) on Section 4.18: Finite limits and colimits

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked.

In your comment you can use Markdown and LaTeX style mathematics (enclose it like $\pi$). A preview option is available if you wish to see how it works out (just click on the eye in the toolbar).

Unfortunately JavaScript is disabled in your browser, so the comment preview function will not work.

All contributions are licensed under the GNU Free Documentation License.