Proof.
Existence: A morphism with all the properties listed exists by combining Lemmas 53.22.6 and 53.23.6 as discussed in the introduction to this section. Moreover, we see that it can be written as a composition
X \to X_1 \to X_2 \ldots \to X_ n \to X_{n + 1} \to \ldots \to X_{n + n'}
where the first n morphisms are contractions of rational tails and the last n' morphisms are contractions of rational bridges. Note that property (2) holds for each contraction of a rational tail (Example 53.22.1) and contraction of a rational bridge (Example 53.23.1). It is easy to see that this property is inherited by compositions of morphisms.
Uniqueness: Let c : X \to Y be a morphism satisfying conditions (1), (2), and (3). We will show that there is a unique isomorphism X_{n + n'} \to Y compatible with the morphisms X \to X_{n + n'} and c.
Before we start the proof we make some observations about c. We first observe that the fibres of c are geometrically connected by More on Morphisms, Theorem 37.53.4. In particular c is surjective. For a closed point y \in Y the fibre X_ y satisfies
H^1(X_ y, \mathcal{O}_{X_ y}) = 0 \quad \text{and}\quad H^0(X_ y, \mathcal{O}_{X_ y}) = \kappa (y)
The first equality by More on Morphisms, Lemma 37.72.1 and the second by More on Morphisms, Lemma 37.72.4. Thus either X_ y = x where x is the unique point of X mapping to y and has the same residue field as y, or X_ y is a 1-dimensional proper scheme over \kappa (y). Observe that in the second case X_ y is Cohen-Macaulay (Lemma 53.6.1). However, since X is reduced, we see that X_ y must be reduced at all of its generic points (details omitted), and hence X_ y is reduced by Properties, Lemma 28.12.4. It follows that the singularities of X_ y are at-worst-nodal (Lemma 53.19.17). Note that the genus of X_ y is zero (see above). Finally, there are only a finite number of points y where the fibre X_ y has dimension 1, say \{ y_1, \ldots , y_ r\} , and c^{-1}(Y \setminus \{ y_1, \ldots , y_ r\} ) maps isomorphically to Y \setminus \{ y_1, \ldots , y_ r\} by c. Some details omitted; hint: outside of \{ y_1, \ldots , y_ r\} the morphism c is finite, see Cohomology of Schemes, Lemma 30.21.1.
Let C \subset X be a rational tail. We claim that c maps C to a point. Assume that this is not the case to get a contradiction. Then the image of C is an irreducible component D \subset Y. Recall that H^0(C, \mathcal{O}_ C) = k' is a finite separable extension of k and that C has a k'-rational point x which is also the unique intersection of C with the “rest” of X. We conclude from the general discussion above that C \setminus \{ x\} \subset c^{-1}(Y \setminus \{ y_1, \ldots , y_ r\} ) maps isomorphically to an open V of D. Let y = c(x) \in D. Observe that y is the only point of D meeting the “rest” of Y. If y \not\in \{ y_1, \ldots , y_ r\} , then C \cong D and it is clear that D is a rational tail of Y which is a contradiction with the ampleness of \omega _ Y (Lemma 53.22.2). Thus y \in \{ y_1, \ldots , y_ r\} and \dim (X_ y) = 1. Then x \in X_ y \cap C and x is a smooth point of X_ y and C (Lemma 53.19.17). If y \in D is a singular point of D, then y is a node and then Y = D (because there cannot be another component of Y passing through y by Lemma 53.19.17). Then X = X_ y \cup C which means g = 0 because it is equal to the genus of X_ y by the discussion in Example 53.22.1; a contradiction. If y \in D is a smooth point of D, then C \to D is an isomorphism (because the nonsingular projective model is unique and C and D are birational, see Section 53.2). Then D is a rational tail of Y which is a contradiction with ampleness of \omega _ Y.
Assume n \geq 1. If C \subset X is the rational tail contracted by X \to X_1, then we see that C is mapped to a point of Y by the previous paragraph. Hence c : X \to Y factors through X \to X_1 (because X is the pushout of C and X_1, see discussion in Example 53.22.1). After replacing X by X_1 we have decreased n. By induction we may assume n = 0, i.e., X does not have a rational tail.
Assume n = 0, i.e., X does not have any rational tails. Then \omega _ X^{\otimes 2} and \omega _ X^{\otimes 3} are globally generated by Lemma 53.22.5. It follows that H^1(X, \omega _ X^{\otimes 3}) = 0 by Lemma 53.6.4. By Lemma 53.24.1 applied with m = 3 we find that c^*\omega _ Y \cong \omega _ X. We also have that \omega _ X = (X \to X_{n'})^*\omega _{X_{n'}} by Lemma 53.23.4 and induction. Applying the projection formula for both c and X \to X_{n'} we conclude that
\Gamma (X_{n'}, \omega _{X_{n'}}^{\otimes m}) = \Gamma (X, \omega _ X^{\otimes m}) = \Gamma (Y, \omega _ Y^{\otimes m})
for all m. Since X_{n'} and Y are the Proj of the direct sum of these by Morphisms, Lemma 29.43.17 we conclude that there is a canonical isomorphism X_{n'} = Y as desired. We omit the verification that this is the unique isomorphism making the diagram commute.
\square
Comments (2)
Comment #5463 by Leo on
Comment #5679 by Johan on