Processing math: 100%

The Stacks project

7.8 Families of morphisms with fixed target

This section is meant to introduce some notions regarding families of morphisms with the same target.

Definition 7.8.1. Let \mathcal{C} be a category. Let \mathcal{U} = \{ U_ i \to U\} _{i\in I} be a family of morphisms of \mathcal{C} with fixed target. Let \mathcal{V} = \{ V_ j \to V\} _{j\in J} be another.

  1. A morphism of families of maps with fixed target of \mathcal{C} from \mathcal{U} to \mathcal{V}, or simply a morphism from \mathcal{U} to \mathcal{V} is given by a morphism U \to V, a map of sets \alpha : I \to J and for each i\in I a morphism U_ i \to V_{\alpha (i)} such that the diagram

    \xymatrix{ U_ i \ar[r] \ar[d] & V_{\alpha (i)} \ar[d] \\ U \ar[r] & V }

    is commutative.

  2. In the special case that U = V and U \to V is the identity we call \mathcal{U} a refinement of the family \mathcal{V}.

A trivial but important remark is that if \mathcal{V} = \{ V_ j \to V\} _{j \in J} is the empty family of maps, i.e., if J = \emptyset , then no family \mathcal{U} = \{ U_ i \to V\} _{i \in I} with I \not= \emptyset can refine \mathcal{V}!

Definition 7.8.2. Let \mathcal{C} be a category. Let \mathcal{U} = \{ \varphi _ i : U_ i \to U\} _{i\in I}, and \mathcal{V} = \{ \psi _ j : V_ j \to U\} _{j\in J} be two families of morphisms with fixed target.

  1. We say \mathcal{U} and \mathcal{V} are combinatorially equivalent if there exist maps \alpha : I \to J and \beta : J\to I such that \varphi _ i = \psi _{\alpha (i)} and \psi _ j = \varphi _{\beta (j)}.

  2. We say \mathcal{U} and \mathcal{V} are tautologically equivalent if there exist maps \alpha : I \to J and \beta : J\to I and for all i\in I and j \in J commutative diagrams

    \xymatrix{ U_ i \ar[rd] \ar[rr] & & V_{\alpha (i)} \ar[ld] & & V_ j \ar[rd] \ar[rr] & & U_{\beta (j)} \ar[ld] \\ & U & & & & U & }

    with isomorphisms as horizontal arrows.

Lemma 7.8.3. Let \mathcal{C} be a category. Let \mathcal{U} = \{ \varphi _ i : U_ i \to U\} _{i\in I}, and \mathcal{V} = \{ \psi _ j : V_ j \to U\} _{j\in J} be two families of morphisms with the same fixed target.

  1. If \mathcal{U} and \mathcal{V} are combinatorially equivalent then they are tautologically equivalent.

  2. If \mathcal{U} and \mathcal{V} are tautologically equivalent then \mathcal{U} is a refinement of \mathcal{V} and \mathcal{V} is a refinement of \mathcal{U}.

  3. The relation “being combinatorially equivalent” is an equivalence relation on all families of morphisms with fixed target.

  4. The relation “being tautologically equivalent” is an equivalence relation on all families of morphisms with fixed target.

  5. The relation “\mathcal{U} refines \mathcal{V} and \mathcal{V} refines \mathcal{U}” is an equivalence relation on all families of morphisms with fixed target.

Proof. Omitted. \square

In the following lemma, given a category \mathcal{C}, a presheaf \mathcal{F} on \mathcal{C}, a family \mathcal{U} = \{ U_ i \to U\} _{i\in I} such that all fibre products U_ i \times _ U U_{i'} exist, we say that the sheaf condition for \mathcal{F} with respect to \mathcal{U} holds if the diagram (7.7.1.1) is an equalizer diagram.

Lemma 7.8.4. Let \mathcal{C} be a category. Let \mathcal{U} = \{ \varphi _ i : U_ i \to U\} _{i\in I}, and \mathcal{V} = \{ \psi _ j : V_ j \to U\} _{j\in J} be two families of morphisms with the same fixed target. Assume that the fibre products U_ i \times _ U U_{i'} and V_ j \times _ U V_{j'} exist. If \mathcal{U} and \mathcal{V} are tautologically equivalent, then for any presheaf \mathcal{F} on \mathcal{C} the sheaf condition for \mathcal{F} with respect to \mathcal{U} is equivalent to the sheaf condition for \mathcal{F} with respect to \mathcal{V}.

Proof. First, note that if \varphi : A \to B is an isomorphism in the category \mathcal{C}, then \varphi ^* : \mathcal{F}(B) \to \mathcal{F}(A) is an isomorphism. Let \beta : J \to I be a map and let \chi _ j : V_ j \to U_{\beta (j)} be isomorphisms over U which are assumed to exist by hypothesis. Let us show that the sheaf condition for \mathcal{V} implies the sheaf condition for \mathcal{U}. Suppose given sections s_ i \in \mathcal{F}(U_ i) such that

s_ i|_{U_ i \times _ U U_{i'}} = s_{i'}|_{U_ i \times _ U U_{i'}}

in \mathcal{F}(U_ i \times _ U U_{i'}) for all pairs (i, i') \in I \times I. Then we can define s_ j = \chi _ j^*s_{\beta (j)}. For any pair (j, j') \in J \times J the morphism \chi _ j \times _{\text{id}_ U} \chi _{j'} : V_ j \times _ U V_{j'} \to U_{\beta (j)} \times _ U U_{\beta (j')} is an isomorphism as well. Hence by transport of structure we see that

s_ j|_{V_ j \times _ U V_{j'}} = s_{j'}|_{V_ j \times _ U V_{j'}}

as well. The sheaf condition w.r.t. \mathcal{V} implies there exists a unique s such that s|_{V_ j} = s_ j for all j \in J. By the first remark of the proof this implies that s|_{U_ i} = s_ i for all i \in \mathop{\mathrm{Im}}(\beta ) as well. Suppose that i \in I, i \not\in \mathop{\mathrm{Im}}(\beta ). For such an i we have isomorphisms U_ i \to V_{\alpha (i)} \to U_{\beta (\alpha (i))} over U. This gives a morphism U_ i \to U_ i \times _ U U_{\beta (\alpha (i))} which is a section of the projection. Because s_ i and s_{\beta (\alpha (i))} restrict to the same element on the fibre product we conclude that s_{\beta (\alpha (i))} pulls back to s_ i via U_ i \to U_{\beta (\alpha (i))}. Thus we see that also s_ i = s|_{U_ i} as desired. \square

Lemma 7.8.5. Let \mathcal{C} be a category. Let \mathcal{V} = \{ V_ j \to U\} _{j \in J} \to \mathcal{U} = \{ U_ i \to U\} _{i \in I} be a morphism of families of maps with fixed target of \mathcal{C} given by \text{id} : U \to U, \alpha : J \to I and f_ j : V_ j \to U_{\alpha (j)}. Let \mathcal{F} be a presheaf on \mathcal{C}. If \mathcal{F}(U) \to \prod _{j \in J} \mathcal{F}(V_ j) is injective then \mathcal{F}(U) \to \prod _{i \in I} \mathcal{F}(U_ i) is injective.

Proof. Omitted. \square

Lemma 7.8.6. Let \mathcal{C} be a category. Let \mathcal{V} = \{ V_ j \to U\} _{j \in J} \to \mathcal{U} = \{ U_ i \to U\} _{i \in I} be a morphism of families of maps with fixed target of \mathcal{C} given by \text{id} : U \to U, \alpha : J \to I and f_ j : V_ j \to U_{\alpha (j)}. Let \mathcal{F} be a presheaf on \mathcal{C}. If

  1. the fibre products U_ i \times _ U U_{i'}, U_ i \times _ U V_ j, V_ j \times _ U V_{j'} exist,

  2. \mathcal{F} satisfies the sheaf condition with respect to \mathcal{V}, and

  3. for every i \in I the map \mathcal{F}(U_ i) \to \prod _{j \in J} \mathcal{F}(V_ j \times _ U U_ i) is injective.

Then \mathcal{F} satisfies the sheaf condition with respect to \mathcal{U}.

Proof. By Lemma 7.8.5 the map \mathcal{F}(U) \to \prod \mathcal{F}(U_ i) is injective. Suppose given s_ i \in \mathcal{F}(U_ i) such that s_ i|_{U_ i \times _ U U_{i'}} = s_{i'}|_{U_ i \times _ U U_{i'}} for all i, i' \in I. Set s_ j = f_ j^*(s_{\alpha (j)}) \in \mathcal{F}(V_ j). Since the morphisms f_ j are morphisms over U we obtain induced morphisms f_{jj'} : V_ j \times _ U V_{j'} \to U_{\alpha (i)} \times _ U U_{\alpha (i')} compatible with the f_ j, f_{j'} via the projection maps. It follows that

s_ j|_{V_ j \times _ U V_{j'}} = f_{jj'}^*(s_{\alpha (j)}|_{U_{\alpha (j)} \times _ U U_{\alpha (j')}}) = f_{jj'}^*(s_{\alpha (j')}|_{U_{\alpha (j)} \times _ U U_{\alpha (j')}}) = s_{j'}|_{V_ j \times _ U V_{j'}}

for all j, j' \in J. Hence, by the sheaf condition for \mathcal{F} with respect to \mathcal{V}, we get a section s \in \mathcal{F}(U) which restricts to s_ j on each V_ j. We are done if we show s restricts to s_ i on U_ i for any i \in I. Since \mathcal{F} satisfies (3) it suffices to show that s and s_ i restrict to the same element over U_ i \times _ U V_ j for all j \in J. To see this we use

s|_{U_ i \times _ U V_ j} = s_ j|_{U_ i \times _ U V_ j} = (\text{id} \times f_ j)^*s_{\alpha (j)}|_{U_ i \times _ U U_{\alpha (j)}} = (\text{id} \times f_ j)^*s_ i|_{U_ i \times _ U U_{\alpha (j)}} = s_ i|_{U_ i \times _ U V_ j}

as desired. \square

Lemma 7.8.7. Let \mathcal{C} be a category. Let \text{Cov}_ i, i = 1, 2 be two sets of families of morphisms with fixed target which each define the structure of a site on \mathcal{C}.

  1. If every \mathcal{U} \in \text{Cov}_1 is tautologically equivalent to some \mathcal{V} \in \text{Cov}_2, then \mathop{\mathit{Sh}}\nolimits (\mathcal{C}, \text{Cov}_2) \subset \mathop{\mathit{Sh}}\nolimits (\mathcal{C}, \text{Cov}_1). If also, every \mathcal{U} \in \text{Cov}_2 is tautologically equivalent to some \mathcal{V} \in \text{Cov}_1 then the category of sheaves are equal.

  2. Suppose that for each \mathcal{U} \in \text{Cov}_1 there exists a \mathcal{V} \in \text{Cov}_2 such that \mathcal{V} refines \mathcal{U}. In this case \mathop{\mathit{Sh}}\nolimits (\mathcal{C}, \text{Cov}_2) \subset \mathop{\mathit{Sh}}\nolimits (\mathcal{C}, \text{Cov}_1). If also for every \mathcal{U} \in \text{Cov}_2 there exists a \mathcal{V} \in \text{Cov}_1 such that \mathcal{V} refines \mathcal{U}, then the categories of sheaves are equal.

Proof. Part (1) follows directly from Lemma 7.8.4 and the definitions.

Proof of (2). Let \mathcal{F} be a sheaf of sets for the site (\mathcal{C}, \text{Cov}_2). Let \mathcal{U} \in \text{Cov}_1, say \mathcal{U} = \{ U_ i \to U\} _{i \in I}. By assumption we may choose a refinement \mathcal{V} \in \text{Cov}_2 of \mathcal{U}, say \mathcal{V} = \{ V_ j \to U\} _{j \in J} and refinement given by \alpha : J \to I and f_ j : V_ j \to U_{\alpha (j)}. Observe that \mathcal{F} satisfies the sheaf condition for \mathcal{V} and for the coverings \{ V_ j \times _ U U_ i \to U_ i\} _{j \in J} as these are in \text{Cov}_2. Hence \mathcal{F} satisfies the sheaf condition for \mathcal{U} by Lemma 7.8.6. \square

Lemma 7.8.8. Let \mathcal{C} be a category. Let \text{Cov}(\mathcal{C}) be a proper class of coverings satisfying conditions (1), (2) and (3) of Definition 7.6.2. Let \text{Cov}_1, \text{Cov}_2 \subset \text{Cov}(\mathcal{C}) be two subsets of \text{Cov}(\mathcal{C}) which endow \mathcal{C} with the structure of a site. If every covering \mathcal{U} \in \text{Cov}(\mathcal{C}) is combinatorially equivalent to a covering in \text{Cov}_1 and combinatorially equivalent to a covering in \text{Cov}_2, then \mathop{\mathit{Sh}}\nolimits (\mathcal{C}, \text{Cov}_1) = \mathop{\mathit{Sh}}\nolimits (\mathcal{C}, \text{Cov}_2).

Proof. This is clear from Lemmas 7.8.7 and 7.8.3 above as the hypothesis implies that every covering \mathcal{U} \in \text{Cov}_1 \subset \text{Cov}(\mathcal{C}) is combinatorially equivalent to an element of \text{Cov}_2, and similarly with the roles of \text{Cov}_1 and \text{Cov}_2 reversed. \square


Comments (6)

Comment #862 by Amit Hogadi on

minor typo: In 7.8.5 line 4, 'quivalent' should be 'equivalent'

Comment #2308 by Dominic Wynter on

Minor typo: in the comment after the first definition, the definition of should read , and not .

Comment #5801 by Bryan Shih on

By the definition of morphism of families, 00VT, seems incompatible with the lemmas later on where seems to be a map from rather than , i.e. 0G1L. Or am I missing something?

Comment #5809 by on

Thanks for pointing this out. I only found one place where the arrow was in the wrong direction but it was confusing ideed. See changes in this commit.


Post a comment

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked.

In your comment you can use Markdown and LaTeX style mathematics (enclose it like $\pi$). A preview option is available if you wish to see how it works out (just click on the eye in the toolbar).

Unfortunately JavaScript is disabled in your browser, so the comment preview function will not work.

All contributions are licensed under the GNU Free Documentation License.




In order to prevent bots from posting comments, we would like you to prove that you are human. You can do this by filling in the name of the current tag in the following input field. As a reminder, this is tag 00VS. Beware of the difference between the letter 'O' and the digit '0'.