The Stacks project

49.8 The Dedekind different

Let $A \to B$ be a ring map. We say the Dedekind different is defined if $A$ is Noetherian, $A \to B$ is finite, any nonzerodivisor on $A$ is a nonzerodivisor on $B$, and $K \to L$ is étale where $K = Q(A)$ and $L = B \otimes _ A K$. Then $K \subset L$ is finite étale and

\[ \mathcal{L}_{B/A} = \{ x \in L \mid \text{Trace}_{L/K}(bx) \in A \text{ for all }b \in B\} \]

is the Dedekind complementary module. In this situation the Dedekind different is

\[ \mathfrak {D}_{B/A} = \{ x \in L \mid x\mathcal{L}_{B/A} \subset B\} \]

viewed as a $B$-submodule of $L$. By Lemma 49.8.1 the Dedekind different is an ideal of $B$ either if $A$ is normal or if $B$ is flat over $A$.

Lemma 49.8.1. Assume the Dedekind different of $A \to B$ is defined. Consider the statements

  1. $A \to B$ is flat,

  2. $A$ is a normal ring,

  3. $\text{Trace}_{L/K}(B) \subset A$,

  4. $1 \in \mathcal{L}_{B/A}$, and

  5. the Dedekind different $\mathfrak {D}_{B/A}$ is an ideal of $B$.

Then we have (1) $\Rightarrow $ (3), (2) $\Rightarrow $ (3), (3) $\Leftrightarrow $ (4), and (4) $\Rightarrow $ (5).

Proof. The equivalence of (3) and (4) and the implication (4) $\Rightarrow $ (5) are immediate.

If $A \to B$ is flat, then we see that $\text{Trace}_{B/A} : B \to A$ is defined and that $\text{Trace}_{L/K}$ is the base change. Hence (3) holds.

If $A$ is normal, then $A$ is a finite product of normal domains, hence we reduce to the case of a normal domain. Then $K$ is the fraction field of $A$ and $L = \prod L_ i$ is a finite product of finite separable field extensions of $K$. Then $\text{Trace}_{L/K}(b) = \sum \text{Trace}_{L_ i/K}(b_ i)$ where $b_ i \in L_ i$ is the image of $b$. Since $b$ is integral over $A$ as $B$ is finite over $A$, these traces are in $A$. This is true because the minimal polynomial of $b_ i$ over $K$ has coefficients in $A$ (Algebra, Lemma 10.38.6) and because $\text{Trace}_{L_ i/K}(b_ i)$ is an integer multiple of one of these coefficients (Fields, Lemma 9.20.3). $\square$

Lemma 49.8.2. If the Dedekind different of $A \to B$ is defined, then there is a canonical isomorphism $\mathcal{L}_{B/A} \to \omega _{B/A}$.

Proof. Recall that $\omega _{B/A} = \mathop{\mathrm{Hom}}\nolimits _ A(B, A)$ as $A \to B$ is finite. We send $x \in \mathcal{L}_{B/A}$ to the map $b \mapsto \text{Trace}_{L/K}(bx)$. Conversely, given an $A$-linear map $\varphi : B \to A$ we obtain a $K$-linear map $\varphi _ K : L \to K$. Since $K \to L$ is finite étale, we see that the trace pairing is nondegenerate (Lemma 49.3.1) and hence there exists a $x \in L$ such that $\varphi _ K(y) = \text{Trace}_{L/K}(xy)$ for all $y \in L$. Then $x \in \mathcal{L}_{B/A}$ maps to $\varphi $ in $\omega _{B/A}$. $\square$

Lemma 49.8.3. If the Dedekind different of $A \to B$ is defined and $A \to B$ is flat, then

  1. the canonical isomorphism $\mathcal{L}_{B/A} \to \omega _{B/A}$ sends $1 \in \mathcal{L}_{B/A}$ to the trace element $\tau _{B/A} \in \omega _{B/A}$, and

  2. the Dedekind different is $\mathfrak {D}_{B/A} = \{ b \in B \mid b\omega _{B/A} \subset B\tau _{B/A}\} $.

Proof. The first assertion follows from the proof of Lemma 49.8.1 and Lemma 49.4.3. The second assertion is immediate from the first and the definitions. $\square$


Comments (0)


Post a comment

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked.

In your comment you can use Markdown and LaTeX style mathematics (enclose it like $\pi$). A preview option is available if you wish to see how it works out (just click on the eye in the toolbar).

Unfortunately JavaScript is disabled in your browser, so the comment preview function will not work.

All contributions are licensed under the GNU Free Documentation License.




In order to prevent bots from posting comments, we would like you to prove that you are human. You can do this by filling in the name of the current tag in the following input field. As a reminder, this is tag 0BW0. Beware of the difference between the letter 'O' and the digit '0'.