Definition 13.40.1. Let \mathcal{D} be an additive category. Let \mathcal{A} \subset \mathcal{D} be a full subcategory. The right orthogonal \mathcal{A}^\perp of \mathcal{A} is the full subcategory consisting of the objects X of \mathcal{D} such that \mathop{\mathrm{Hom}}\nolimits (A, X) = 0 for all A \in \mathop{\mathrm{Ob}}\nolimits (\mathcal{A}). The left orthogonal {}^\perp \mathcal{A} of \mathcal{A} is the full subcategory consisting of the objects X of \mathcal{D} such that \mathop{\mathrm{Hom}}\nolimits (X, A) = 0 for all A \in \mathop{\mathrm{Ob}}\nolimits (\mathcal{A}).
13.40 Admissible subcategories
A reference for this section is [Section 1, Bondal-Kapranov].
Lemma 13.40.2. Let \mathcal{D} be a triangulated category. Let \mathcal{A} \subset \mathcal{D} be a full subcategory invariant under all shifts. Consider a distinguished triangle
of \mathcal{D}. The following are equivalent
Z is in \mathcal{A}^\perp , and
\mathop{\mathrm{Hom}}\nolimits (A, X) = \mathop{\mathrm{Hom}}\nolimits (A, Y) for all A \in \mathop{\mathrm{Ob}}\nolimits (\mathcal{A}).
Proof. By Lemma 13.4.2 the functor \mathop{\mathrm{Hom}}\nolimits (A, -) is homological and hence we get a long exact sequence as in (13.3.5.1). Assume (1) and let A \in \mathop{\mathrm{Ob}}\nolimits (\mathcal{A}). Then we consider the exact sequence
Since A[1] \in \mathop{\mathrm{Ob}}\nolimits (\mathcal{A}) we see that the first and last groups are zero. Thus we get (2). Assume (2) and let A \in \mathop{\mathrm{Ob}}\nolimits (\mathcal{A}). Then we consider the exact sequence
and we conclude that \mathop{\mathrm{Hom}}\nolimits (A, Z) = 0 as desired. \square
Lemma 13.40.3. Let \mathcal{D} be a triangulated category. Let \mathcal{B} \subset \mathcal{D} be a full subcategory invariant under all shifts. Consider a distinguished triangle
of \mathcal{D}. The following are equivalent
X is in {}^\perp \mathcal{B}, and
\mathop{\mathrm{Hom}}\nolimits (Y, B) = \mathop{\mathrm{Hom}}\nolimits (Z, B) for all B \in \mathop{\mathrm{Ob}}\nolimits (\mathcal{B}).
Proof. Dual to Lemma 13.40.2. \square
Lemma 13.40.4. Let \mathcal{D} be a triangulated category. Let \mathcal{A} \subset \mathcal{D} be a full subcategory invariant under all shifts. Then both the right orthogonal \mathcal{A}^\perp and the left orthogonal {}^\perp \mathcal{A} of \mathcal{A} are strictly full, saturated1, triangulated subcagories of \mathcal{D}.
Proof. It is immediate from the definitions that the orthogonals are preserved under taking shifts, direct sums, and direct summands. Consider a distinguished triangle
of \mathcal{D}. By Lemma 13.4.16 it suffices to show that if X and Y are in \mathcal{A}^\perp , then Z is in \mathcal{A}^\perp . This is immediate from Lemma 13.40.2. \square
Lemma 13.40.5. Let \mathcal{D} be a triangulated category. Let \mathcal{A} be a full triangulated subcategory of \mathcal{D}. For an object X of \mathcal{D} consider the property P(X): there exists a distinguished triangle A \to X \to B \to A[1] in \mathcal{D} with A in \mathcal{A} and B in \mathcal{A}^\perp .
If X_1 \to X_2 \to X_3 \to X_1[1] is a distinguished triangle and P holds for two out of three, then it holds for the third.
If P holds for X_1 and X_2, then it holds for X_1 \oplus X_2.
Proof. Let X_1 \to X_2 \to X_3 \to X_1[1] be a distinguished triangle and assume P holds for X_1 and X_2. Choose distinguished triangles
as in condition P. Since \mathop{\mathrm{Hom}}\nolimits (A_1, A_2) = \mathop{\mathrm{Hom}}\nolimits (A_1, X_2) by Lemma 13.40.2 there is a unique morphism A_1 \to A_2 such that the diagram
commutes. Choose an extension of this to a diagram
as in Proposition 13.4.23. By TR3 we see that Q_1 \cong B_1 and Q_2 \cong B_2 and hence Q_1, Q_2 \in \mathop{\mathrm{Ob}}\nolimits (\mathcal{A}^\perp ). As Q_1 \to Q_2 \to Q_3 \to Q_1[1] is a distinguished triangle we see that Q_3 \in \mathop{\mathrm{Ob}}\nolimits (\mathcal{A}^\perp ) by Lemma 13.40.4. Since \mathcal{A} is a full triangulated subcategory, we see that A_3 is isomorphic to an object of \mathcal{A}. Thus X_3 satisfies P. The other cases of (1) follow from this case by translation. Part (2) is a special case of (1) via Lemma 13.4.11. \square
Lemma 13.40.6. Let \mathcal{D} be a triangulated category. Let \mathcal{B} be a full triangulated subcategory of \mathcal{D}. For an object X of \mathcal{D} consider the property P(X): there exists a distinguished triangle A \to X \to B \to A[1] in \mathcal{D} with B in \mathcal{B} and A in {}^\perp \mathcal{B}.
If X_1 \to X_2 \to X_3 \to X_1[1] is a distinguished triangle and P holds for two out of three, then it holds for the third.
If P holds for X_1 and X_2, then it holds for X_1 \oplus X_2.
Proof. Dual to Lemma 13.40.5. \square
Lemma 13.40.7. Let \mathcal{D} be a triangulated category. Let \mathcal{A} \subset \mathcal{D} be a full triangulated subcategory. The following are equivalent
the inclusion functor \mathcal{A} \to \mathcal{D} has a right adjoint, and
for every X in \mathcal{D} there exists a distinguished triangle
A \to X \to B \to A[1]in \mathcal{D} with A \in \mathop{\mathrm{Ob}}\nolimits (\mathcal{A}) and B \in \mathop{\mathrm{Ob}}\nolimits (\mathcal{A}^\perp ).
If this holds, then \mathcal{A} is saturated (Definition 13.6.1) and if \mathcal{A} is strictly full in \mathcal{D}, then \mathcal{A} = {}^\perp (\mathcal{A}^\perp ).
Proof. Assume (1) and denote v : \mathcal{D} \to \mathcal{A} the right adjoint. Let X \in \mathop{\mathrm{Ob}}\nolimits (\mathcal{D}). Set A = v(X). We may extend the adjunction mapping A \to X to a distinguished triangle A \to X \to B \to A[1]. Since
for A' \in \mathop{\mathrm{Ob}}\nolimits (\mathcal{A}), we conclude that B \in \mathop{\mathrm{Ob}}\nolimits (\mathcal{A}^\perp ) by Lemma 13.40.2.
Assume (2). We will construct the adjoint v explicitly. Let X \in \mathop{\mathrm{Ob}}\nolimits (\mathcal{D}). Choose A \to X \to B \to A[1] as in (2). Set v(X) = A. Let f : X \to Y be a morphism in \mathcal{D}. Choose A' \to Y \to B' \to A'[1] as in (2). Since \mathop{\mathrm{Hom}}\nolimits (A, A') = \mathop{\mathrm{Hom}}\nolimits (A, Y) by Lemma 13.40.2 there is a unique morphism f' : A \to A' such that the diagram
commutes. Hence we can set v(f) = f' to get a functor. To see that v is adjoint to the inclusion morphism use Lemma 13.40.2 again.
Proof of the final statement. In order to prove that \mathcal{A} is saturated we may replace \mathcal{A} by the strictly full subcategory having the same isomorphism classes as \mathcal{A}; details omitted. Assume \mathcal{A} is strictly full. If we show that \mathcal{A} = {}^\perp (\mathcal{A}^\perp ), then \mathcal{A} will be saturated by Lemma 13.40.4. Since the incusion \mathcal{A} \subset {}^\perp (\mathcal{A}^\perp ) is clear it suffices to prove the other inclusion. Let X be an object of {}^\perp (\mathcal{A}^\perp ). Choose a distinguished triangle A \to X \to B \to A[1] as in (2). As \mathop{\mathrm{Hom}}\nolimits (X, B) = 0 by assumption we see that A \cong X \oplus B[-1] by Lemma 13.4.11. Since \mathop{\mathrm{Hom}}\nolimits (A, B[-1]) = 0 as B \in \mathcal{A}^\perp this implies B[-1] = 0 and A \cong X as desired. \square
Lemma 13.40.8. Let \mathcal{D} be a triangulated category. Let \mathcal{B} \subset \mathcal{D} be a full triangulated subcategory. The following are equivalent
the inclusion functor \mathcal{B} \to \mathcal{D} has a left adjoint, and
for every X in \mathcal{D} there exists a distinguished triangle
A \to X \to B \to A[1]in \mathcal{D} with B \in \mathop{\mathrm{Ob}}\nolimits (\mathcal{B}) and A \in \mathop{\mathrm{Ob}}\nolimits ({}^\perp \mathcal{B}).
If this holds, then \mathcal{B} is saturated (Definition 13.6.1) and if \mathcal{B} is strictly full in \mathcal{D}, then \mathcal{B} = ({}^\perp \mathcal{B})^\perp .
Proof. Dual to Lemma 13.40.7. \square
Definition 13.40.9. Let \mathcal{D} be a triangulated category. A right admissible subcategory of \mathcal{D} is a strictly full triangulated subcategory satisfying the equivalent conditions of Lemma 13.40.7. A left admissible subcategory of \mathcal{D} is a strictly full triangulated subcategory satisfying the equivalent conditions of Lemma 13.40.8. A two-sided admissible subcategory is one which is both right and left admissible.
Let \mathcal{A} be a right admissible subcategory of the triangulated category \mathcal{D}. Then we observe that for X \in \mathcal{D} the distinguished triangle
with A \in \mathcal{A} and B \in \mathcal{A}^\perp is canonical in the following sense: for any other distinguished triangle A' \to X \to B' \to A'[1] with A' \in \mathcal{A} and B' \in \mathcal{A}^\perp there is an isomorphism (\alpha , \text{id}_ X, \beta ) : (A, X, B) \to (A', X, B') of triangles. The following proposition summarizes what was said above.
Proposition 13.40.10. Let \mathcal{D} be a triangulated category. Let \mathcal{A} \subset \mathcal{D} and \mathcal{B} \subset \mathcal{D} be subcategories. The following are equivalent
\mathcal{A} is right admissible and \mathcal{B} = \mathcal{A}^\perp ,
\mathcal{B} is left admissible and \mathcal{A} = {}^\perp \mathcal{B},
\mathop{\mathrm{Hom}}\nolimits (A, B) = 0 for all A \in \mathcal{A} and B \in \mathcal{B} and for every X in \mathcal{D} there exists a distinguished triangle A \to X \to B \to A[1] in \mathcal{D} with A \in \mathcal{A} and B \in \mathcal{B}.
If this is true, then \mathcal{A} \to \mathcal{D}/\mathcal{B} and \mathcal{B} \to \mathcal{D}/\mathcal{A} are equivalences of triangulated categories, the right adjoint to the inclusion functor \mathcal{A} \to \mathcal{D} is \mathcal{D} \to \mathcal{D}/\mathcal{B} \to \mathcal{A}, and the left adjoint to the inclusion functor \mathcal{B} \to \mathcal{D} is \mathcal{D} \to \mathcal{D}/\mathcal{A} \to \mathcal{B}.
Proof. The equivalence between (1), (2), and (3) follows in a straightforward manner from Lemmas 13.40.7 and 13.40.8 (small detail omitted). Denote v : \mathcal{D} \to \mathcal{A} the right adjoint of the inclusion functor i : \mathcal{A} \to \mathcal{D}. It is immediate that \mathop{\mathrm{Ker}}(v) = \mathcal{A}^\perp = \mathcal{B}. Thus v factors over a functor \overline{v} : \mathcal{D}/\mathcal{B} \to \mathcal{A} by the universal property of the quotient. Since v \circ i = \text{id}_\mathcal {A} by Categories, Lemma 4.24.4 we see that \overline{v} is a left quasi-inverse to \overline{i} : \mathcal{A} \to \mathcal{D}/\mathcal{B}. We claim also the composition \overline{i} \circ \overline{v} is isomorphic to \text{id}_{\mathcal{D}/\mathcal{B}}. Namely, suppose we have X fitting into a distinguished triangle A \to X \to B \to A[1] as in (3). Then v(X) = A as was seen in the proof of Lemma 13.40.7. Viewing X as an object of \mathcal{D}/\mathcal{B} we have \overline{i}(\overline{v}(X)) = A and there is a functorial isomorphism \overline{i}(\overline{v}(X)) = A \to X in \mathcal{D}/\mathcal{B}. Thus we find that indeed \overline{v} : \mathcal{D}/\mathcal{B} \to \mathcal{A} is an equivalence. To show that \mathcal{B} \to \mathcal{D}/\mathcal{A} is an equivalence and the left adjoint to the inclusion functor \mathcal{B} \to \mathcal{D} is \mathcal{D} \to \mathcal{D}/\mathcal{A} \to \mathcal{B} is dual to what we just said. \square
Comments (3)
Comment #6021 by Sandeep on
Comment #6022 by Sandeep on
Comment #6172 by Johan on