The Stacks project

12.8 Localization

In this section we note how Gabriel-Zisman localization interacts with the additive structure on a category.

Lemma 12.8.1. Let $\mathcal{C}$ be a preadditive category. Let $S$ be a left or right multiplicative system. There exists a unique preadditive structure on $S^{-1}\mathcal{C}$ such that the localization functor $Q : \mathcal{C} \to S^{-1}\mathcal{C}$ is additive.

Proof. We will prove this in the case $S$ is a left multiplicative system. The case where $S$ is a right multiplicative system is dual. Suppose that $X, Y$ are objects of $\mathcal{C}$ and that $\alpha , \beta : X \to Y$ are morphisms in $S^{-1}\mathcal{C}$. According to Categories, Lemma 4.27.5 we may represent these by pairs $s^{-1}f, s^{-1}g$ with common denominator $s$. Suppose that we have a pre-additive structure on $S^{-1}\mathcal{C}$ and that $Q$ is additive. Then

\begin{align*} s^{-1}f+s^{-1}g & =Q(s)^{-1}\circ Q(f)+Q(s)^{-1}\circ Q(g)\\ & =Q(s)^{-1}\circ (Q(f)+Q(g))\\ & =Q(s)^{-1}\circ Q(f+g)\\ & =s^{-1}(f+g). \end{align*}

Hence, the pre-additive structure on $S^{-1}\mathcal{C}$ is unique if it exists. Correspondingly, we define $\alpha + \beta $ to be the equivalence class of $s^{-1}(f + g)$ and in the rest of the proof we show that this is well defined and that composition is bilinear. Once this is done it is clear that $Q$ is an additive functor.

Let us show construction above is well defined. An abstract way of saying this is that filtered colimits of abelian groups agree with filtered colimits of sets and to use Categories, Equation (4.27.7.1). We can work this out in a bit more detail as follows. Say $s : Y \to Y_1$ and $f, g : X \to Y_1$. Suppose we have a second representation of $\alpha , \beta $ as $(s')^{-1}f', (s')^{-1}g'$ with $s' : Y \to Y_2$ and $f', g' : X \to Y_2$. By Categories, Remark 4.27.7 we can find a morphism $s_3 : Y \to Y_3$ and morphisms $a_1 : Y_1 \to Y_3$, $a_2 : Y_2 \to Y_3$ such that $a_1 \circ s = s_3 = a_2 \circ s'$ and also $a_1 \circ f = a_2 \circ f'$ and $a_1 \circ g = a_2 \circ g'$. Hence we see that $s^{-1}(f + g)$ is equivalent to

\begin{align*} s_3^{-1}(a_1 \circ (f + g)) & = s_3^{-1}(a_1 \circ f + a_1 \circ g) \\ & = s_3^{-1}(a_2 \circ f' + a_2 \circ g') \\ & = s_3^{-1}(a_2 \circ (f' + g')) \end{align*}

which is equivalent to $(s')^{-1}(f' + g')$.

Fix $s : Y \to Y'$ and $f, g : X \to Y'$ with $\alpha = s^{-1}f$ and $\beta = s^{-1}g$ as morphisms $X \to Y$ in $S^{-1}\mathcal{C}$. To show that composition is bilinear first consider the case of a morphism $\gamma : Y \to Z$ in $S^{-1}\mathcal{C}$. Say $\gamma = t^{-1}h$ for some $h : Y \to Z'$ and $t : Z \to Z'$ in $S$. Using LMS2 we choose morphisms $a : Y' \to Z''$ and $t' : Z' \to Z''$ in $S$ such that $a \circ s = t' \circ h$. Picture

\[ \xymatrix{ & & Z \ar[d]^ t \\ & Y \ar[r]^ h \ar[d]^ s & Z' \ar[d]^{t'} \\ X \ar[r]^{f, g} & Y' \ar[r]^ a & Z'' } \]

Then $\gamma \circ \alpha = (t' \circ t)^{-1}(a \circ f)$ and $\gamma \circ \beta = (t' \circ t)^{-1}(a \circ g)$. Hence we see that $\gamma \circ (\alpha + \beta )$ is represented by $(t' \circ t)^{-1}(a \circ (f + g)) = (t' \circ t)^{-1}(a \circ f + a \circ g)$ which represents $\gamma \circ \alpha + \gamma \circ \beta $.

Finally, assume that $\delta : W \to X$ is another morphism of $S^{-1}\mathcal{C}$. Say $\delta = r^{-1}i$ for some $i : W \to X'$ and $r : X \to X'$ in $S$. We claim that we can find a morphism $s' : Y' \to Y''$ in $S$ and morphisms $a'', b'' : X' \to Y''$ such that the following diagram commutes

\[ \xymatrix{ & & & Y \ar[d]^ s \\ & X \ar[rr]^{f, g, f + g} \ar[d]^ r & & Y' \ar[d]^{s'} \\ W \ar[r]^ i & X' \ar[rr]^{a'', b'', a'' + b''} & & Y'' } \]

Namely, using LMS2 we can first choose $s_1 : Y' \to Y_1$, $s_2 : Y' \to Y_2$ in $S$ and $a : X' \to Y_1$, $b : X' \to Y_2$ such that $a \circ r = s_1 \circ f$ and $b \circ r = s_2 \circ f$. Then using that the category $Y'/S$ is filtered (see Categories, Remark 4.27.7), we can find a $s' : Y' \to Y''$ and morphisms $a' : Y_1 \to Y''$, $b' : Y_2 \to Y''$ such that $s' = a' \circ s_1$ and $s' = b' \circ s_2$. Setting $a'' = a' \circ a$ and $b'' = b' \circ b$ works. At this point we see that the compositions $\alpha \circ \delta $ and $\beta \circ \delta $ are represented by $(s' \circ s)^{-1}(a'' \circ i)$ and $(s' \circ s)^{-1}(b'' \circ i)$. Hence $\alpha \circ \delta + \beta \circ \delta $ is represented by $(s' \circ s)^{-1}(a'' \circ i + b'' \circ i) = (s' \circ s)^{-1}((a'' + b'') \circ i)$ which by the diagram again is a representative of $(\alpha + \beta ) \circ \delta $. $\square$

Lemma 12.8.2. Let $\mathcal{C}$ be an additive category. Let $S$ be a left or right multiplicative system. Then $S^{-1}\mathcal{C}$ is an additive category and the localization functor $Q : \mathcal{C} \to S^{-1}\mathcal{C}$ is additive.

Proof. By Lemma 12.8.1 we see that $S^{-1}\mathcal{C}$ is preadditive and that $Q$ is additive. Recall that the functor $Q$ commutes with finite colimits (resp. finite limits), see Categories, Lemmas 4.27.9 and 4.27.17. We conclude that $S^{-1}\mathcal{C}$ has a zero object and direct sums, see Lemmas 12.3.2 and 12.3.4. $\square$

The following lemma describes the “kernel” of the localization functor in case we invert a multiplicative system.

Lemma 12.8.3. Let $\mathcal{C}$ be an additive category. Let $S$ be a multiplicative system. Let $X$ be an object of $\mathcal{C}$. The following are equivalent

  1. $Q(X) = 0$ in $S^{-1}\mathcal{C}$,

  2. there exists $Y \in \mathop{\mathrm{Ob}}\nolimits (\mathcal{C})$ such that $0 : X \to Y$ is an element of $S$, and

  3. there exists $Z \in \mathop{\mathrm{Ob}}\nolimits (\mathcal{C})$ such that $0 : Z \to X$ is an element of $S$.

Proof. If (2) holds we see that $0 = Q(0) : Q(X) \to Q(Y)$ is an isomorphism. In the additive category $S^{-1}\mathcal{C}$ this implies that $Q(X) = 0$. Hence (2) $\Rightarrow $ (1). Similarly, (3) $\Rightarrow $ (1). Suppose that $Q(X) = 0$. This implies that the morphism $f : 0 \to X$ is transformed into an isomorphism in $S^{-1}\mathcal{C}$. Hence by Categories, Lemma 4.27.21 there exists a morphism $g : Z \to 0$ such that $fg \in S$. This proves (1) $\Rightarrow $ (3). Similarly, (1) $\Rightarrow $ (2). $\square$

Lemma 12.8.4. Let $\mathcal{A}$ be an abelian category.

  1. If $S$ is a left multiplicative system, then the category $S^{-1}\mathcal{A}$ has cokernels and the functor $Q : \mathcal{A} \to S^{-1}\mathcal{A}$ commutes with them.

  2. If $S$ is a right multiplicative system, then the category $S^{-1}\mathcal{A}$ has kernels and the functor $Q : \mathcal{A} \to S^{-1}\mathcal{A}$ commutes with them.

  3. If $S$ is a multiplicative system, then the category $S^{-1}\mathcal{A}$ is abelian and the functor $Q : \mathcal{A} \to S^{-1}\mathcal{A}$ is exact.

Proof. Assume $S$ is a left multiplicative system. Let $a : X \to Y$ be a morphism of $S^{-1}\mathcal{A}$. Then $a = s^{-1}f$ for some $s : Y \to Y'$ in $S$ and $f : X \to Y'$. Since $Q(s)$ is an isomorphism we see that the existence of $\mathop{\mathrm{Coker}}(a : X \to Y)$ is equivalent to the existence of $\mathop{\mathrm{Coker}}(Q(f) : X \to Y')$. Since $\mathop{\mathrm{Coker}}(Q(f))$ is the coequalizer of $0$ and $Q(f)$ we see that $\mathop{\mathrm{Coker}}(Q(f))$ is represented by $Q(\mathop{\mathrm{Coker}}(f))$ by Categories, Lemma 4.27.9. This proves (1).

Part (2) is dual to part (1).

If $S$ is a multiplicative system, then $S$ is both a left and a right multiplicative system. Thus we see that $S^{-1}\mathcal{A}$ has kernels and cokernels and $Q$ commutes with kernels and cokernels. To finish the proof of (3) we have to show that $\mathop{\mathrm{Coim}}= \mathop{\mathrm{Im}}$ in $S^{-1}\mathcal{A}$. Again using that any arrow in $S^{-1}\mathcal{A}$ is isomorphic to an arrow $Q(f)$ we see that the result follows from the result for $\mathcal{A}$. $\square$


Comments (3)

Comment #5886 by Anna Cadoret on

This is a stupid comment but the notion of kernel in 10.12.5 is only introduced for an additive functor between Abelian categories while, here, it is used in the more general context of an additive functor between additive categories.

Comment #6091 by on

OK, you are right. I fixed this for now by removing the reference to Definition 12.10.5 and using scarequotes around the word kernel. See here.

Comment #9465 by on

For future reference, and in case anyone wants to chime in. To this section, I would add the following result:

Lemma. Let be a preadditive category. Let be a LMS in . Let be a morphism in . Then if and only if there exists in with .

Proof. This is a particular case of Categories, Lemma 4.27.6.

This was originally proposed in #8372.


Post a comment

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked.

In your comment you can use Markdown and LaTeX style mathematics (enclose it like $\pi$). A preview option is available if you wish to see how it works out (just click on the eye in the toolbar).

Unfortunately JavaScript is disabled in your browser, so the comment preview function will not work.

All contributions are licensed under the GNU Free Documentation License.




In order to prevent bots from posting comments, we would like you to prove that you are human. You can do this by filling in the name of the current tag in the following input field. As a reminder, this is tag 05QC. Beware of the difference between the letter 'O' and the digit '0'.