The Stacks project

93.10 Morphisms of Schemes

The deformation theory of morphisms of schemes. Of course this is just an example of deformations of diagrams of schemes.

Example 93.10.1 (Morphisms of schemes). Let $\mathcal{F}$ be the category defined as follows

  1. an object is a pair $(A, X \to Y)$ consisting of an object $A$ of $\mathcal{C}_\Lambda $ and a morphism $X \to Y$ of schemes over $A$ with both $X$ and $Y$ flat over $A$, and

  2. a morphism $(f, g, h) : (A', X' \to Y') \to (A, X \to Y)$ consists of a morphism $f : A' \to A$ in $\mathcal{C}_\Lambda $ together with morphisms of schemes $g : X \to X'$ and $h : Y \to Y'$ such that

    \[ \xymatrix{ X \ar[r]_ g \ar[d] & X' \ar[d] \\ Y \ar[r]_ h \ar[d] & Y' \ar[d] \\ \mathop{\mathrm{Spec}}(A) \ar[r]^ f & \mathop{\mathrm{Spec}}(A') } \]

    is a commutative diagram of schemes where both squares are cartesian.

The functor $p : \mathcal{F} \to \mathcal{C}_\Lambda $ sends $(A, X \to Y)$ to $A$ and $(f, g, h)$ to $f$. It is clear that $p$ is cofibred in groupoids. Given a morphism of schemes $X \to Y$ over $k$, let $x_0 = (k, X \to Y)$ be the corresponding object of $\mathcal{F}(k)$. We set

\[ \mathcal{D}\! \mathit{ef}_{X \to Y} = \mathcal{F}_{x_0} \]

Lemma 93.10.2. Example 93.10.1 satisfies the Rim-Schlessinger condition (RS). In particular, $\mathcal{D}\! \mathit{ef}_{X \to Y}$ is a deformation category for any morphism of schemes $X \to Y$ over $k$.

Proof. Let $A_1 \to A$ and $A_2 \to A$ be morphisms of $\mathcal{C}_\Lambda $. Assume $A_2 \to A$ is surjective. According to Formal Deformation Theory, Lemma 90.16.4 it suffices to show that the functor $\mathcal{F}(A_1 \times _ A A_2) \to \mathcal{F}(A_1) \times _{\mathcal{F}(A)} \mathcal{F}(A_2)$ is an equivalence of categories. Observe that

\[ \xymatrix{ \mathop{\mathrm{Spec}}(A) \ar[r] \ar[d] & \mathop{\mathrm{Spec}}(A_2) \ar[d] \\ \mathop{\mathrm{Spec}}(A_1) \ar[r] & \mathop{\mathrm{Spec}}(A_1 \times _ A A_2) } \]

is a pushout diagram as in More on Morphisms, Lemma 37.14.3. Thus the lemma follows immediately from More on Morphisms, Lemma 37.14.6 as this describes the category of schemes flat over $A_1 \times _ A A_2$ as the fibre product of the category of schemes flat over $A_1$ with the category of schemes flat over $A_2$ over the category of schemes flat over $A$. $\square$

Lemma 93.10.3. In Example 93.9.1 let $f : X \to Y$ be a morphism of schemes over $k$. There is a canonical exact sequence of $k$-vector spaces

\[ \xymatrix{ 0 \ar[r] & \text{Inf}(\mathcal{D}\! \mathit{ef}_{X \to Y}) \ar[r] & \text{Inf}(\mathcal{D}\! \mathit{ef}_ X \times \mathcal{D}\! \mathit{ef}_ Y) \ar[r] & \text{Der}_ k(\mathcal{O}_ Y, f_*\mathcal{O}_ X) \ar[lld] \\ & T\mathcal{D}\! \mathit{ef}_{X \to Y} \ar[r] & T(\mathcal{D}\! \mathit{ef}_ X \times \mathcal{D}\! \mathit{ef}_ Y) \ar[r] & \text{Ext}^1_{\mathcal{O}_ X}(Lf^*\mathop{N\! L}\nolimits _{Y/k}, \mathcal{O}_ X) } \]

Proof. The obvious map of deformation categories $\mathcal{D}\! \mathit{ef}_{X \to Y} \to \mathcal{D}\! \mathit{ef}_ X \times \mathcal{D}\! \mathit{ef}_ Y$ gives two of the arrows in the exact sequence of the lemma. Recall that $\text{Inf}(\mathcal{D}\! \mathit{ef}_{X \to Y})$ is the set of automorphisms of the trivial deformation

\[ f' : X' = X \times _{\mathop{\mathrm{Spec}}(k)} \mathop{\mathrm{Spec}}(k[\epsilon ]) \xrightarrow {f \times \text{id}} Y' = Y \times _{\mathop{\mathrm{Spec}}(k)} \mathop{\mathrm{Spec}}(k[\epsilon ]) \]

of $X \to Y$ to $k[\epsilon ]$ equal to the identity modulo $\epsilon $. This is clearly the same thing as pairs $(\alpha , \beta ) \in \text{Inf}(\mathcal{D}\! \mathit{ef}_ X \times \mathcal{D}\! \mathit{ef}_ Y)$ of infinitesimal automorphisms of $X$ and $Y$ compatible with $f'$, i.e., such that $f' \circ \alpha = \beta \circ f'$. By Deformation Theory, Lemma 91.7.1 for an arbitrary pair $(\alpha , \beta )$ the difference between the morphism $f' : X' \to Y'$ and the morphism $\beta ^{-1} \circ f' \circ \alpha : X' \to Y'$ defines an element in

\[ \text{Der}_ k(\mathcal{O}_ Y, f_*\mathcal{O}_ X) = \mathop{\mathrm{Hom}}\nolimits _{\mathcal{O}_ Y}(\Omega _{Y/k}, f_*\mathcal{O}_ X) \]

Equality by More on Morphisms, Lemma 37.13.3. This defines the last top horizontal arrow and shows exactness in the first two places. For the map

\[ \text{Der}_ k(\mathcal{O}_ Y, f_*\mathcal{O}_ X) \to T\mathcal{D}\! \mathit{ef}_{X \to Y} \]

we interpret elements of the source as morphisms $f_\epsilon : X' \to Y'$ over $\mathop{\mathrm{Spec}}(k[\epsilon ])$ equal to $f$ modulo $\epsilon $ using Deformation Theory, Lemma 91.7.1. We send $f_\epsilon $ to the isomorphism class of $(f_\epsilon : X' \to Y')$ in $T\mathcal{D}\! \mathit{ef}_{X \to Y}$. Note that $(f_\epsilon : X' \to Y')$ is isomorphic to the trivial deformation $(f' : X' \to Y')$ exactly when $f_\epsilon = \beta ^{-1} \circ f \circ \alpha $ for some pair $(\alpha , \beta )$ which implies exactness in the third spot. Clearly, if some first order deformation $(f_\epsilon : X_\epsilon \to Y_\epsilon )$ maps to zero in $T(\mathcal{D}\! \mathit{ef}_ X \times \mathcal{D}\! \mathit{ef}_ Y)$, then we can choose isomorphisms $X' \to X_\epsilon $ and $Y' \to Y_\epsilon $ and we conclude we are in the image of the south-west arrow. Therefore we have exactness at the fourth spot. Finally, given two first order deformations $X_\epsilon $, $Y_\epsilon $ of $X$, $Y$ there is an obstruction in

\[ ob(X_\epsilon , Y_\epsilon ) \in \text{Ext}^1_{\mathcal{O}_ X}(Lf^*\mathop{N\! L}\nolimits _{Y/k}, \mathcal{O}_ X) \]

which vanishes if and only if $f : X \to Y$ lifts to $X_\epsilon \to Y_\epsilon $, see Deformation Theory, Lemma 91.7.1. This finishes the proof. $\square$

Lemma 93.10.4. In Lemma 93.10.3 if $X$ and $Y$ are both proper over $k$, then $\text{Inf}(\mathcal{D}\! \mathit{ef}_{X \to Y})$ and $T\mathcal{D}\! \mathit{ef}_{X \to Y}$ are finite dimensional.

Proof. Omitted. Hint: argue as in Lemma 93.9.4 and use the exact sequence of the lemma. $\square$

In Example 93.10.1 if $X \to Y$ is a morphism of proper schemes over $k$, then $\mathcal{D}\! \mathit{ef}_{X \to Y}$ admits a presentation by a smooth prorepresentable groupoid in functors over $\mathcal{C}_\Lambda $ and a fortiori has a (minimal) versal formal object. This follows from Lemmas 93.10.2 and 93.10.4 and the general discussion in Section 93.3.

Lemma 93.10.5. In Example 93.10.1 assume $X \to Y$ is a morphism of proper $k$-schemes. Assume $\Lambda $ is a complete local ring with residue field $k$ (the classical case). Then the functor

\[ F : \mathcal{C}_\Lambda \longrightarrow \textit{Sets},\quad A \longmapsto \mathop{\mathrm{Ob}}\nolimits (\mathcal{D}\! \mathit{ef}_{X \to Y}(A))/\cong \]

of isomorphism classes of objects has a hull. If $\text{Der}_ k(\mathcal{O}_ X, \mathcal{O}_ X) = \text{Der}_ k(\mathcal{O}_ Y, \mathcal{O}_ Y) = 0$, then $F$ is prorepresentable.

Proof. The existence of a hull follows immediately from Lemmas 93.10.2 and 93.10.4 and Formal Deformation Theory, Lemma 90.16.6 and Remark 90.15.7.

Assume $\text{Der}_ k(\mathcal{O}_ X, \mathcal{O}_ X) = \text{Der}_ k(\mathcal{O}_ Y, \mathcal{O}_ Y) = 0$. Then the exact sequence of Lemma 93.10.3 combined with Lemma 93.9.3 shows that $\text{Inf}(\mathcal{D}\! \mathit{ef}_{X \to Y}) = 0$. Then $\mathcal{D}\! \mathit{ef}_{X \to Y}$ and $F$ are equivalent by Formal Deformation Theory, Lemma 90.19.13. Hence $F$ is a deformation functor (because $\mathcal{D}\! \mathit{ef}_{X \to Y}$ is a deformation category) with finite tangent space and we can apply Formal Deformation Theory, Theorem 90.18.2. $\square$

reference

Lemma 93.10.6. In Example 93.9.1 let $f : X \to Y$ be a morphism of schemes over $k$. If $f_*\mathcal{O}_ X = \mathcal{O}_ Y$ and $R^1f_*\mathcal{O}_ X = 0$, then the morphism of deformation categories

\[ \mathcal{D}\! \mathit{ef}_{X \to Y} \to \mathcal{D}\! \mathit{ef}_ X \]

is an equivalence.

Proof. We construct a quasi-inverse to the forgetful functor of the lemma. Namely, suppose that $(A, U)$ is an object of $\mathcal{D}\! \mathit{ef}_ X$. The given map $X \to U$ is a finite order thickening and we can use it to identify the underlying topological spaces of $U$ and $X$, see More on Morphisms, Section 37.2. Thus we may and do think of $\mathcal{O}_ U$ as a sheaf of $A$-algebras on $X$; moreover the fact that $U \to \mathop{\mathrm{Spec}}(A)$ is flat, means that $\mathcal{O}_ U$ is flat as a sheaf of $A$-modules. In particular, we have a filtration

\[ 0 = \mathfrak m_ A^ n\mathcal{O}_ U \subset \mathfrak m_ A^{n - 1}\mathcal{O}_ U \subset \ldots \subset \mathfrak m_ A^2\mathcal{O}_ U \subset \mathfrak m_ A\mathcal{O}_ U \subset \mathcal{O}_ U \]

with subquotients equal to $\mathcal{O}_ X \otimes _ k \mathfrak m_ A^ i/\mathfrak m_ A^{i + 1}$ by flatness, see More on Morphisms, Lemma 37.10.1 or the more general Deformation Theory, Lemma 91.5.2. Set

\[ \mathcal{O}_ V = f_*\mathcal{O}_ U \]

viewed as sheaf of $A$-algebras on $Y$. Since $R^1f_*\mathcal{O}_ X = 0$ we find by the description above that $R^1f_*(\mathfrak m_ A^ i\mathcal{O}_ U/\mathfrak m_ A^{i + 1}\mathcal{O}_ U) = 0$ for all $i$. This implies that the sequences

\[ 0 \to (f_*\mathcal{O}_ X) \otimes _ k \mathfrak m_ A^ i/\mathfrak m_ A^{i + 1} \to f_*(\mathcal{O}_ U/\mathfrak m_ A^{i + 1}\mathcal{O}_ U) \to f_*(\mathcal{O}_ U/\mathfrak m_ A^ i\mathcal{O}_ U) \to 0 \]

are exact for all $i$. Reading the references given above backwards (and using induction) we find that $\mathcal{O}_ V$ is a flat sheaf of $A$-algebras with $\mathcal{O}_ V/\mathfrak m_ A\mathcal{O}_ V = \mathcal{O}_ Y$. Using More on Morphisms, Lemma 37.2.2 we find that $(Y, \mathcal{O}_ V)$ is a scheme, call it $V$. The equality $\mathcal{O}_ V = f_*\mathcal{O}_ U$ defines a morphism of ringed spaces $U \to V$ which is easily seen to be a morphism of schemes. This finishes the proof by the flatness already established. $\square$


Comments (2)

Comment #3578 by on

In the statement of Lemma 0E3V, the morphism X --> Y should be called f (as f appears in the assertion), and then the second sentence of the proof can be omitted.

Comment #3702 by on

Thanks Ben! A rare change that shrinks the Stacks project... See changes here.


Post a comment

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked.

In your comment you can use Markdown and LaTeX style mathematics (enclose it like $\pi$). A preview option is available if you wish to see how it works out (just click on the eye in the toolbar).

Unfortunately JavaScript is disabled in your browser, so the comment preview function will not work.

All contributions are licensed under the GNU Free Documentation License.




In order to prevent bots from posting comments, we would like you to prove that you are human. You can do this by filling in the name of the current tag in the following input field. As a reminder, this is tag 0E3S. Beware of the difference between the letter 'O' and the digit '0'.